Proof of the principle of backwards inductionBackward induction (Tao Analysis vol. 1).Backward induction (Tao Analysis vol. 1).Proof for Strong Induction PrincipleInduction Proof with FactorialsProof of induction principle, Proof falsificationDifference between downward induction and infinite descentMathematical induction from $n=1$Two questions about proof by inductionAm I permitted to use the truth of the base case during the inductive step in a proof using weak induction?Evaluate my proof of strong induction (Analysis I, Tao)Terry Tao's strong induction formulation

My adviser wants to be the first author

I need to drive a 7/16" nut but am unsure how to use the socket I bought for my screwdriver

Do I need life insurance if I can cover my own funeral costs?

Instead of Universal Basic Income, why not Universal Basic NEEDS?

How do anti-virus programs start at Windows boot?

Why does Deadpool say "You're welcome, Canada," after shooting Ryan Reynolds in the end credits?

Is it possible to upcast ritual spells?

Happy pi day, everyone!

Did CPM support custom hardware using device drivers?

Current sense amp + op-amp buffer + ADC: Measuring down to 0 with single supply

How to simplify this time periods definition interface?

Good allowance savings plan?

Should we release the security issues we found in our product as CVE or we can just update those on weekly release notes?

What does it mean to make a bootable LiveUSB?

How can I change step-down my variable input voltage? [Microcontroller]

Does the statement `int val = (++i > ++j) ? ++i : ++j;` invoke undefined behavior?

Make a transparent 448*448 image

What are some nice/clever ways to introduce the tonic's dominant seventh chord?

Theorems like the Lovász Local Lemma?

How could a female member of a species produce eggs unto death?

At what level can a dragon innately cast its spells?

Why are there 40 737 Max planes in flight when they have been grounded as not airworthy?

Ban on all campaign finance?

Professor being mistaken for a grad student



Proof of the principle of backwards induction


Backward induction (Tao Analysis vol. 1).Backward induction (Tao Analysis vol. 1).Proof for Strong Induction PrincipleInduction Proof with FactorialsProof of induction principle, Proof falsificationDifference between downward induction and infinite descentMathematical induction from $n=1$Two questions about proof by inductionAm I permitted to use the truth of the base case during the inductive step in a proof using weak induction?Evaluate my proof of strong induction (Analysis I, Tao)Terry Tao's strong induction formulation













2












$begingroup$


I have difficulty in neatly writing down a proof for the following:




Let $n$ be a natural number, and let $P(m)$ be a property pertaining to the natural numbers such that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, then $P(m)$ is true. Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true. Prove that $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $mleq n$; this is know as the principle of backwards induction. (Hint: apply induction to the variable $n$.)




First of all, I am unsure about what the base case should look like. For the induction step, I understand that if we suppose inductively that $P(n)$ is true, that then for a natural number $a$ s.t. $a++=n$ it holds that $P(a)$ is true, and then for a natural number $b$ s.t. $b++=a$ it holds that $P(b)$ is true etc. Hence for all natural numbers $mleq n$, $P(m)$ is true.



Could anyone please tell me what the base case should look like, and whether there is a neater way of writing down the induction step?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    Seems to me that the hint is a little misleading. The way I would approach this is try to prove that for any $a leq n$, $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $n - a leq m leq n$, by induction on $a$.
    $endgroup$
    – Scaramouche
    Jul 31 '13 at 17:46






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    What does $a++=n$ mean?
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 '13 at 17:52










  • $begingroup$
    This question was asked the other day (or at least a very similar question), see here.
    $endgroup$
    – Kenny Hegeland
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:00











  • $begingroup$
    I also believe that rbm is reading from Tao's analysis where he uses $++$ to represent the successor when constructing $BbbN$ from the Peano axioms.
    $endgroup$
    – Kenny Hegeland
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:04







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Using $++$ is by all means a horrible mathematical notation. In particular since $+$ itself is already in the language and is a binary operator. Using $s$ or $S$ is much clearer and common enough, at least in logic.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:29















2












$begingroup$


I have difficulty in neatly writing down a proof for the following:




Let $n$ be a natural number, and let $P(m)$ be a property pertaining to the natural numbers such that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, then $P(m)$ is true. Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true. Prove that $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $mleq n$; this is know as the principle of backwards induction. (Hint: apply induction to the variable $n$.)




First of all, I am unsure about what the base case should look like. For the induction step, I understand that if we suppose inductively that $P(n)$ is true, that then for a natural number $a$ s.t. $a++=n$ it holds that $P(a)$ is true, and then for a natural number $b$ s.t. $b++=a$ it holds that $P(b)$ is true etc. Hence for all natural numbers $mleq n$, $P(m)$ is true.



Could anyone please tell me what the base case should look like, and whether there is a neater way of writing down the induction step?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    Seems to me that the hint is a little misleading. The way I would approach this is try to prove that for any $a leq n$, $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $n - a leq m leq n$, by induction on $a$.
    $endgroup$
    – Scaramouche
    Jul 31 '13 at 17:46






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    What does $a++=n$ mean?
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 '13 at 17:52










  • $begingroup$
    This question was asked the other day (or at least a very similar question), see here.
    $endgroup$
    – Kenny Hegeland
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:00











  • $begingroup$
    I also believe that rbm is reading from Tao's analysis where he uses $++$ to represent the successor when constructing $BbbN$ from the Peano axioms.
    $endgroup$
    – Kenny Hegeland
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:04







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Using $++$ is by all means a horrible mathematical notation. In particular since $+$ itself is already in the language and is a binary operator. Using $s$ or $S$ is much clearer and common enough, at least in logic.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:29













2












2








2





$begingroup$


I have difficulty in neatly writing down a proof for the following:




Let $n$ be a natural number, and let $P(m)$ be a property pertaining to the natural numbers such that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, then $P(m)$ is true. Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true. Prove that $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $mleq n$; this is know as the principle of backwards induction. (Hint: apply induction to the variable $n$.)




First of all, I am unsure about what the base case should look like. For the induction step, I understand that if we suppose inductively that $P(n)$ is true, that then for a natural number $a$ s.t. $a++=n$ it holds that $P(a)$ is true, and then for a natural number $b$ s.t. $b++=a$ it holds that $P(b)$ is true etc. Hence for all natural numbers $mleq n$, $P(m)$ is true.



Could anyone please tell me what the base case should look like, and whether there is a neater way of writing down the induction step?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I have difficulty in neatly writing down a proof for the following:




Let $n$ be a natural number, and let $P(m)$ be a property pertaining to the natural numbers such that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, then $P(m)$ is true. Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true. Prove that $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $mleq n$; this is know as the principle of backwards induction. (Hint: apply induction to the variable $n$.)




First of all, I am unsure about what the base case should look like. For the induction step, I understand that if we suppose inductively that $P(n)$ is true, that then for a natural number $a$ s.t. $a++=n$ it holds that $P(a)$ is true, and then for a natural number $b$ s.t. $b++=a$ it holds that $P(b)$ is true etc. Hence for all natural numbers $mleq n$, $P(m)$ is true.



Could anyone please tell me what the base case should look like, and whether there is a neater way of writing down the induction step?







elementary-set-theory induction






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jul 31 '13 at 18:06









Stefan Hamcke

21.8k42880




21.8k42880










asked Jul 31 '13 at 17:43









dreamerdreamer

1,68143062




1,68143062











  • $begingroup$
    Seems to me that the hint is a little misleading. The way I would approach this is try to prove that for any $a leq n$, $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $n - a leq m leq n$, by induction on $a$.
    $endgroup$
    – Scaramouche
    Jul 31 '13 at 17:46






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    What does $a++=n$ mean?
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 '13 at 17:52










  • $begingroup$
    This question was asked the other day (or at least a very similar question), see here.
    $endgroup$
    – Kenny Hegeland
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:00











  • $begingroup$
    I also believe that rbm is reading from Tao's analysis where he uses $++$ to represent the successor when constructing $BbbN$ from the Peano axioms.
    $endgroup$
    – Kenny Hegeland
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:04







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Using $++$ is by all means a horrible mathematical notation. In particular since $+$ itself is already in the language and is a binary operator. Using $s$ or $S$ is much clearer and common enough, at least in logic.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:29
















  • $begingroup$
    Seems to me that the hint is a little misleading. The way I would approach this is try to prove that for any $a leq n$, $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $n - a leq m leq n$, by induction on $a$.
    $endgroup$
    – Scaramouche
    Jul 31 '13 at 17:46






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    What does $a++=n$ mean?
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 '13 at 17:52










  • $begingroup$
    This question was asked the other day (or at least a very similar question), see here.
    $endgroup$
    – Kenny Hegeland
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:00











  • $begingroup$
    I also believe that rbm is reading from Tao's analysis where he uses $++$ to represent the successor when constructing $BbbN$ from the Peano axioms.
    $endgroup$
    – Kenny Hegeland
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:04







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Using $++$ is by all means a horrible mathematical notation. In particular since $+$ itself is already in the language and is a binary operator. Using $s$ or $S$ is much clearer and common enough, at least in logic.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:29















$begingroup$
Seems to me that the hint is a little misleading. The way I would approach this is try to prove that for any $a leq n$, $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $n - a leq m leq n$, by induction on $a$.
$endgroup$
– Scaramouche
Jul 31 '13 at 17:46




$begingroup$
Seems to me that the hint is a little misleading. The way I would approach this is try to prove that for any $a leq n$, $P(m)$ is true for all natural numbers $n - a leq m leq n$, by induction on $a$.
$endgroup$
– Scaramouche
Jul 31 '13 at 17:46




2




2




$begingroup$
What does $a++=n$ mean?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 31 '13 at 17:52




$begingroup$
What does $a++=n$ mean?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 31 '13 at 17:52












$begingroup$
This question was asked the other day (or at least a very similar question), see here.
$endgroup$
– Kenny Hegeland
Jul 31 '13 at 18:00





$begingroup$
This question was asked the other day (or at least a very similar question), see here.
$endgroup$
– Kenny Hegeland
Jul 31 '13 at 18:00













$begingroup$
I also believe that rbm is reading from Tao's analysis where he uses $++$ to represent the successor when constructing $BbbN$ from the Peano axioms.
$endgroup$
– Kenny Hegeland
Jul 31 '13 at 18:04





$begingroup$
I also believe that rbm is reading from Tao's analysis where he uses $++$ to represent the successor when constructing $BbbN$ from the Peano axioms.
$endgroup$
– Kenny Hegeland
Jul 31 '13 at 18:04





1




1




$begingroup$
Using $++$ is by all means a horrible mathematical notation. In particular since $+$ itself is already in the language and is a binary operator. Using $s$ or $S$ is much clearer and common enough, at least in logic.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 31 '13 at 18:29




$begingroup$
Using $++$ is by all means a horrible mathematical notation. In particular since $+$ itself is already in the language and is a binary operator. Using $s$ or $S$ is much clearer and common enough, at least in logic.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 31 '13 at 18:29










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















1












$begingroup$

This answer is to show the statement can be proved on (upward) induction on $n$, as in the hint.



Suppose the statement holds at a specific $n$. The statement of it for $n++$ is then:



Suppose $P(n++)$ is true, then it follows that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$



From the assumption that $P(n++) implies P(n),$ we arrive at $P(n)$ true, so that from the inductive hypothesis $P(k)$ holds for all $k le n$. Together with the assumption that $P(n++)$ holds, we have the desired conclusion of the inductive step, i.e. that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Great! Thanks a lot!
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Jul 31 '13 at 19:41










  • $begingroup$
    One question that came up, what would you say is the base case (did you include that in your answer)?
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Aug 1 '13 at 9:58






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @rbm No I didn't since it seems too obvious. It would just say (for $n=1$): Suppose $P(1)$ holds. Then $P(m)$ holds for all $m le 1$. But there's only one such $m$, namely $1$, so that there is nothing to show for the base case.
    $endgroup$
    – coffeemath
    Aug 1 '13 at 11:04


















4












$begingroup$

Prove, by ordinary induction on $k$, the statement "if $n-kgeq0$ then $P(n-k)$. The base case is $P(n)$, and the induction step, going from $k$ to $k+1$, comes from the "backward induction" hypothesis, because increasing $k$ decreases $n-k$.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Thank you for your help! That is a nice way of converting it to an ordinary induction problem. One question that I have; how exactly does the base case work (why would $P(n)$ hold true)?
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:29







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @rbm $P(n)$ was one of your assumptions in the question; you wrote "Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true."
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Blass
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:43










  • $begingroup$
    It seems that assuming well-ordering of the naturals, it's quite easy for students to prove variants of standard induction (complete, backward, forward-backward...). But to show that these variants hold using standard induction requires students to modify the proposition to be proved (in your case, it's $n-k geq 0 implies P(n-k)$), which students find difficult. Any tips and ideas that students can practise and use to improve this skill?
    $endgroup$
    – Maxis Jaisi
    Mar 3 '17 at 6:54


















0












$begingroup$

Proof: Let $n in mathbbN$. Using induction on $n$, for the base case $n = 0$, we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle 0$. But only $0le 0$ so we just need to show that $P(0)$ is true. Since $P(n)$ is true from the hypothesis, $P(0)$ is true and that completes the base case.



Suppose inductively that the principle if true for $n$, i.e $P$ is such that $P(n)$ is true, and whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n$. We have to show the principle is true for $n++$ i.e we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n++$ given that $P(n++)$ is true and given that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true.



Since $P(n++)$ is true, then $P(n)$ is also true. So we have to show that $P(m)$ is true $m<n$. But from the inductive hypothesis, $P(m)$ is true $forall$ $mle n$ and that completes the induction. $square$






share|cite|improve this answer








New contributor




Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$












    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    );
    );
    , "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function()
    var channelOptions =
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    ;
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
    createEditor();
    );

    else
    createEditor();

    );

    function createEditor()
    StackExchange.prepareEditor(
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader:
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    ,
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    );



    );













    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function ()
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f456589%2fproof-of-the-principle-of-backwards-induction%23new-answer', 'question_page');

    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes








    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    1












    $begingroup$

    This answer is to show the statement can be proved on (upward) induction on $n$, as in the hint.



    Suppose the statement holds at a specific $n$. The statement of it for $n++$ is then:



    Suppose $P(n++)$ is true, then it follows that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$



    From the assumption that $P(n++) implies P(n),$ we arrive at $P(n)$ true, so that from the inductive hypothesis $P(k)$ holds for all $k le n$. Together with the assumption that $P(n++)$ holds, we have the desired conclusion of the inductive step, i.e. that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      Great! Thanks a lot!
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Jul 31 '13 at 19:41










    • $begingroup$
      One question that came up, what would you say is the base case (did you include that in your answer)?
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Aug 1 '13 at 9:58






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @rbm No I didn't since it seems too obvious. It would just say (for $n=1$): Suppose $P(1)$ holds. Then $P(m)$ holds for all $m le 1$. But there's only one such $m$, namely $1$, so that there is nothing to show for the base case.
      $endgroup$
      – coffeemath
      Aug 1 '13 at 11:04















    1












    $begingroup$

    This answer is to show the statement can be proved on (upward) induction on $n$, as in the hint.



    Suppose the statement holds at a specific $n$. The statement of it for $n++$ is then:



    Suppose $P(n++)$ is true, then it follows that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$



    From the assumption that $P(n++) implies P(n),$ we arrive at $P(n)$ true, so that from the inductive hypothesis $P(k)$ holds for all $k le n$. Together with the assumption that $P(n++)$ holds, we have the desired conclusion of the inductive step, i.e. that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      Great! Thanks a lot!
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Jul 31 '13 at 19:41










    • $begingroup$
      One question that came up, what would you say is the base case (did you include that in your answer)?
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Aug 1 '13 at 9:58






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @rbm No I didn't since it seems too obvious. It would just say (for $n=1$): Suppose $P(1)$ holds. Then $P(m)$ holds for all $m le 1$. But there's only one such $m$, namely $1$, so that there is nothing to show for the base case.
      $endgroup$
      – coffeemath
      Aug 1 '13 at 11:04













    1












    1








    1





    $begingroup$

    This answer is to show the statement can be proved on (upward) induction on $n$, as in the hint.



    Suppose the statement holds at a specific $n$. The statement of it for $n++$ is then:



    Suppose $P(n++)$ is true, then it follows that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$



    From the assumption that $P(n++) implies P(n),$ we arrive at $P(n)$ true, so that from the inductive hypothesis $P(k)$ holds for all $k le n$. Together with the assumption that $P(n++)$ holds, we have the desired conclusion of the inductive step, i.e. that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    This answer is to show the statement can be proved on (upward) induction on $n$, as in the hint.



    Suppose the statement holds at a specific $n$. The statement of it for $n++$ is then:



    Suppose $P(n++)$ is true, then it follows that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$



    From the assumption that $P(n++) implies P(n),$ we arrive at $P(n)$ true, so that from the inductive hypothesis $P(k)$ holds for all $k le n$. Together with the assumption that $P(n++)$ holds, we have the desired conclusion of the inductive step, i.e. that $P(m)$ holds for all $m le n++.$







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Jul 31 '13 at 18:37









    coffeemathcoffeemath

    27.3k22342




    27.3k22342











    • $begingroup$
      Great! Thanks a lot!
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Jul 31 '13 at 19:41










    • $begingroup$
      One question that came up, what would you say is the base case (did you include that in your answer)?
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Aug 1 '13 at 9:58






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @rbm No I didn't since it seems too obvious. It would just say (for $n=1$): Suppose $P(1)$ holds. Then $P(m)$ holds for all $m le 1$. But there's only one such $m$, namely $1$, so that there is nothing to show for the base case.
      $endgroup$
      – coffeemath
      Aug 1 '13 at 11:04
















    • $begingroup$
      Great! Thanks a lot!
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Jul 31 '13 at 19:41










    • $begingroup$
      One question that came up, what would you say is the base case (did you include that in your answer)?
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Aug 1 '13 at 9:58






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @rbm No I didn't since it seems too obvious. It would just say (for $n=1$): Suppose $P(1)$ holds. Then $P(m)$ holds for all $m le 1$. But there's only one such $m$, namely $1$, so that there is nothing to show for the base case.
      $endgroup$
      – coffeemath
      Aug 1 '13 at 11:04















    $begingroup$
    Great! Thanks a lot!
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Jul 31 '13 at 19:41




    $begingroup$
    Great! Thanks a lot!
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Jul 31 '13 at 19:41












    $begingroup$
    One question that came up, what would you say is the base case (did you include that in your answer)?
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Aug 1 '13 at 9:58




    $begingroup$
    One question that came up, what would you say is the base case (did you include that in your answer)?
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Aug 1 '13 at 9:58




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    @rbm No I didn't since it seems too obvious. It would just say (for $n=1$): Suppose $P(1)$ holds. Then $P(m)$ holds for all $m le 1$. But there's only one such $m$, namely $1$, so that there is nothing to show for the base case.
    $endgroup$
    – coffeemath
    Aug 1 '13 at 11:04




    $begingroup$
    @rbm No I didn't since it seems too obvious. It would just say (for $n=1$): Suppose $P(1)$ holds. Then $P(m)$ holds for all $m le 1$. But there's only one such $m$, namely $1$, so that there is nothing to show for the base case.
    $endgroup$
    – coffeemath
    Aug 1 '13 at 11:04











    4












    $begingroup$

    Prove, by ordinary induction on $k$, the statement "if $n-kgeq0$ then $P(n-k)$. The base case is $P(n)$, and the induction step, going from $k$ to $k+1$, comes from the "backward induction" hypothesis, because increasing $k$ decreases $n-k$.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      Thank you for your help! That is a nice way of converting it to an ordinary induction problem. One question that I have; how exactly does the base case work (why would $P(n)$ hold true)?
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Jul 31 '13 at 18:29







    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @rbm $P(n)$ was one of your assumptions in the question; you wrote "Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true."
      $endgroup$
      – Andreas Blass
      Jul 31 '13 at 18:43










    • $begingroup$
      It seems that assuming well-ordering of the naturals, it's quite easy for students to prove variants of standard induction (complete, backward, forward-backward...). But to show that these variants hold using standard induction requires students to modify the proposition to be proved (in your case, it's $n-k geq 0 implies P(n-k)$), which students find difficult. Any tips and ideas that students can practise and use to improve this skill?
      $endgroup$
      – Maxis Jaisi
      Mar 3 '17 at 6:54















    4












    $begingroup$

    Prove, by ordinary induction on $k$, the statement "if $n-kgeq0$ then $P(n-k)$. The base case is $P(n)$, and the induction step, going from $k$ to $k+1$, comes from the "backward induction" hypothesis, because increasing $k$ decreases $n-k$.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      Thank you for your help! That is a nice way of converting it to an ordinary induction problem. One question that I have; how exactly does the base case work (why would $P(n)$ hold true)?
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Jul 31 '13 at 18:29







    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @rbm $P(n)$ was one of your assumptions in the question; you wrote "Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true."
      $endgroup$
      – Andreas Blass
      Jul 31 '13 at 18:43










    • $begingroup$
      It seems that assuming well-ordering of the naturals, it's quite easy for students to prove variants of standard induction (complete, backward, forward-backward...). But to show that these variants hold using standard induction requires students to modify the proposition to be proved (in your case, it's $n-k geq 0 implies P(n-k)$), which students find difficult. Any tips and ideas that students can practise and use to improve this skill?
      $endgroup$
      – Maxis Jaisi
      Mar 3 '17 at 6:54













    4












    4








    4





    $begingroup$

    Prove, by ordinary induction on $k$, the statement "if $n-kgeq0$ then $P(n-k)$. The base case is $P(n)$, and the induction step, going from $k$ to $k+1$, comes from the "backward induction" hypothesis, because increasing $k$ decreases $n-k$.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    Prove, by ordinary induction on $k$, the statement "if $n-kgeq0$ then $P(n-k)$. The base case is $P(n)$, and the induction step, going from $k$ to $k+1$, comes from the "backward induction" hypothesis, because increasing $k$ decreases $n-k$.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Jul 31 '13 at 18:22









    Andreas BlassAndreas Blass

    50.2k452109




    50.2k452109











    • $begingroup$
      Thank you for your help! That is a nice way of converting it to an ordinary induction problem. One question that I have; how exactly does the base case work (why would $P(n)$ hold true)?
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Jul 31 '13 at 18:29







    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @rbm $P(n)$ was one of your assumptions in the question; you wrote "Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true."
      $endgroup$
      – Andreas Blass
      Jul 31 '13 at 18:43










    • $begingroup$
      It seems that assuming well-ordering of the naturals, it's quite easy for students to prove variants of standard induction (complete, backward, forward-backward...). But to show that these variants hold using standard induction requires students to modify the proposition to be proved (in your case, it's $n-k geq 0 implies P(n-k)$), which students find difficult. Any tips and ideas that students can practise and use to improve this skill?
      $endgroup$
      – Maxis Jaisi
      Mar 3 '17 at 6:54
















    • $begingroup$
      Thank you for your help! That is a nice way of converting it to an ordinary induction problem. One question that I have; how exactly does the base case work (why would $P(n)$ hold true)?
      $endgroup$
      – dreamer
      Jul 31 '13 at 18:29







    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @rbm $P(n)$ was one of your assumptions in the question; you wrote "Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true."
      $endgroup$
      – Andreas Blass
      Jul 31 '13 at 18:43










    • $begingroup$
      It seems that assuming well-ordering of the naturals, it's quite easy for students to prove variants of standard induction (complete, backward, forward-backward...). But to show that these variants hold using standard induction requires students to modify the proposition to be proved (in your case, it's $n-k geq 0 implies P(n-k)$), which students find difficult. Any tips and ideas that students can practise and use to improve this skill?
      $endgroup$
      – Maxis Jaisi
      Mar 3 '17 at 6:54















    $begingroup$
    Thank you for your help! That is a nice way of converting it to an ordinary induction problem. One question that I have; how exactly does the base case work (why would $P(n)$ hold true)?
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:29





    $begingroup$
    Thank you for your help! That is a nice way of converting it to an ordinary induction problem. One question that I have; how exactly does the base case work (why would $P(n)$ hold true)?
    $endgroup$
    – dreamer
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:29





    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    @rbm $P(n)$ was one of your assumptions in the question; you wrote "Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true."
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Blass
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:43




    $begingroup$
    @rbm $P(n)$ was one of your assumptions in the question; you wrote "Suppose that $P(n)$ is also true."
    $endgroup$
    – Andreas Blass
    Jul 31 '13 at 18:43












    $begingroup$
    It seems that assuming well-ordering of the naturals, it's quite easy for students to prove variants of standard induction (complete, backward, forward-backward...). But to show that these variants hold using standard induction requires students to modify the proposition to be proved (in your case, it's $n-k geq 0 implies P(n-k)$), which students find difficult. Any tips and ideas that students can practise and use to improve this skill?
    $endgroup$
    – Maxis Jaisi
    Mar 3 '17 at 6:54




    $begingroup$
    It seems that assuming well-ordering of the naturals, it's quite easy for students to prove variants of standard induction (complete, backward, forward-backward...). But to show that these variants hold using standard induction requires students to modify the proposition to be proved (in your case, it's $n-k geq 0 implies P(n-k)$), which students find difficult. Any tips and ideas that students can practise and use to improve this skill?
    $endgroup$
    – Maxis Jaisi
    Mar 3 '17 at 6:54











    0












    $begingroup$

    Proof: Let $n in mathbbN$. Using induction on $n$, for the base case $n = 0$, we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle 0$. But only $0le 0$ so we just need to show that $P(0)$ is true. Since $P(n)$ is true from the hypothesis, $P(0)$ is true and that completes the base case.



    Suppose inductively that the principle if true for $n$, i.e $P$ is such that $P(n)$ is true, and whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n$. We have to show the principle is true for $n++$ i.e we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n++$ given that $P(n++)$ is true and given that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true.



    Since $P(n++)$ is true, then $P(n)$ is also true. So we have to show that $P(m)$ is true $m<n$. But from the inductive hypothesis, $P(m)$ is true $forall$ $mle n$ and that completes the induction. $square$






    share|cite|improve this answer








    New contributor




    Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
    Check out our Code of Conduct.






    $endgroup$

















      0












      $begingroup$

      Proof: Let $n in mathbbN$. Using induction on $n$, for the base case $n = 0$, we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle 0$. But only $0le 0$ so we just need to show that $P(0)$ is true. Since $P(n)$ is true from the hypothesis, $P(0)$ is true and that completes the base case.



      Suppose inductively that the principle if true for $n$, i.e $P$ is such that $P(n)$ is true, and whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n$. We have to show the principle is true for $n++$ i.e we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n++$ given that $P(n++)$ is true and given that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true.



      Since $P(n++)$ is true, then $P(n)$ is also true. So we have to show that $P(m)$ is true $m<n$. But from the inductive hypothesis, $P(m)$ is true $forall$ $mle n$ and that completes the induction. $square$






      share|cite|improve this answer








      New contributor




      Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
      Check out our Code of Conduct.






      $endgroup$















        0












        0








        0





        $begingroup$

        Proof: Let $n in mathbbN$. Using induction on $n$, for the base case $n = 0$, we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle 0$. But only $0le 0$ so we just need to show that $P(0)$ is true. Since $P(n)$ is true from the hypothesis, $P(0)$ is true and that completes the base case.



        Suppose inductively that the principle if true for $n$, i.e $P$ is such that $P(n)$ is true, and whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n$. We have to show the principle is true for $n++$ i.e we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n++$ given that $P(n++)$ is true and given that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true.



        Since $P(n++)$ is true, then $P(n)$ is also true. So we have to show that $P(m)$ is true $m<n$. But from the inductive hypothesis, $P(m)$ is true $forall$ $mle n$ and that completes the induction. $square$






        share|cite|improve this answer








        New contributor




        Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
        Check out our Code of Conduct.






        $endgroup$



        Proof: Let $n in mathbbN$. Using induction on $n$, for the base case $n = 0$, we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle 0$. But only $0le 0$ so we just need to show that $P(0)$ is true. Since $P(n)$ is true from the hypothesis, $P(0)$ is true and that completes the base case.



        Suppose inductively that the principle if true for $n$, i.e $P$ is such that $P(n)$ is true, and whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n$. We have to show the principle is true for $n++$ i.e we need to show that $P(m)$ is true $forall mle n++$ given that $P(n++)$ is true and given that whenever $P(m++)$ is true, $P(m)$ is true.



        Since $P(n++)$ is true, then $P(n)$ is also true. So we have to show that $P(m)$ is true $m<n$. But from the inductive hypothesis, $P(m)$ is true $forall$ $mle n$ and that completes the induction. $square$







        share|cite|improve this answer








        New contributor




        Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
        Check out our Code of Conduct.









        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer






        New contributor




        Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
        Check out our Code of Conduct.









        answered Mar 11 at 9:49









        Segun OjoSegun Ojo

        11




        11




        New contributor




        Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
        Check out our Code of Conduct.





        New contributor





        Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
        Check out our Code of Conduct.






        Segun Ojo is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
        Check out our Code of Conduct.



























            draft saved

            draft discarded
















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid


            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f456589%2fproof-of-the-principle-of-backwards-induction%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Solar Wings Breeze Design and development Specifications (Breeze) References Navigation menu1368-485X"Hang glider: Breeze (Solar Wings)"e

            Kathakali Contents Etymology and nomenclature History Repertoire Songs and musical instruments Traditional plays Styles: Sampradayam Training centers and awards Relationship to other dance forms See also Notes References External links Navigation menueThe Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism: A-MSouth Asian Folklore: An EncyclopediaRoutledge International Encyclopedia of Women: Global Women's Issues and KnowledgeKathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to PlayKathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to PlayKathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to Play10.1353/atj.2005.0004The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism: A-MEncyclopedia of HinduismKathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to PlaySonic Liturgy: Ritual and Music in Hindu Tradition"The Mirror of Gesture"Kathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to Play"Kathakali"Indian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceMedieval Indian Literature: An AnthologyThe Oxford Companion to Indian TheatreSouth Asian Folklore: An Encyclopedia : Afghanistan, Bangladesh, India, Nepal, Pakistan, Sri LankaThe Rise of Performance Studies: Rethinking Richard Schechner's Broad SpectrumIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceModern Asian Theatre and Performance 1900-2000Critical Theory and PerformanceBetween Theater and AnthropologyKathakali603847011Indian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceBetween Theater and AnthropologyBetween Theater and AnthropologyNambeesan Smaraka AwardsArchivedThe Cambridge Guide to TheatreRoutledge International Encyclopedia of Women: Global Women's Issues and KnowledgeThe Garland Encyclopedia of World Music: South Asia : the Indian subcontinentThe Ethos of Noh: Actors and Their Art10.2307/1145740By Means of Performance: Intercultural Studies of Theatre and Ritual10.1017/s204912550000100xReconceiving the Renaissance: A Critical ReaderPerformance TheoryListening to Theatre: The Aural Dimension of Beijing Opera10.2307/1146013Kathakali: The Art of the Non-WorldlyOn KathakaliKathakali, the dance theatreThe Kathakali Complex: Performance & StructureKathakali Dance-Drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to Play10.1093/obo/9780195399318-0071Drama and Ritual of Early Hinduism"In the Shadow of Hollywood Orientalism: Authentic East Indian Dancing"10.1080/08949460490274013Sanskrit Play Production in Ancient IndiaIndian Music: History and StructureBharata, the Nāṭyaśāstra233639306Table of Contents2238067286469807Dance In Indian Painting10.2307/32047833204783Kathakali Dance-Theatre: A Visual Narrative of Sacred Indian MimeIndian Classical Dance: The Renaissance and BeyondKathakali: an indigenous art-form of Keralaeee

            Method to test if a number is a perfect power? Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern)Detecting perfect squares faster than by extracting square rooteffective way to get the integer sequence A181392 from oeisA rarely mentioned fact about perfect powersHow many numbers such $n$ are there that $n<100,lfloorsqrtn rfloor mid n$Check perfect squareness by modulo division against multiple basesFor what pair of integers $(a,b)$ is $3^a + 7^b$ a perfect square.Do there exist any positive integers $n$ such that $lfloore^nrfloor$ is a perfect power? What is the probability that one exists?finding perfect power factors of an integerProve that the sequence contains a perfect square for any natural number $m $ in the domain of $f$ .Counting Perfect Powers