Products and the axiom of choice The 2019 Stack Overflow Developer Survey Results Are InUniversal property of the direct product, proof verificationDoes the existence of products in the category of sets imply the Axiom of Choice?Axiom of Choice and Cartesian ProductsConfusion regarding one formulation of the Axiom of Choice.Axiom of Choice (Naive Set Theory, Halmos)Do we need Axiom of Choice to make infinite choices from a set?Why do we need the axiom of choice in showing the non-emptiness of an infinite Cartesian productDefining relations without axiom of choiceProb. 9, Sec. 19 in Munkres' TOPOLOGY, 2nd edition: Equivalence of the choice axiom and non-emptyness of Cartesian productSimple question: Which is the Wikipedia definition of axiom of choiceAxiom of Choice iff Every set has a choice function

Where does the "burst of radiance" from Holy Weapon originate?

Time travel alters history but people keep saying nothing's changed

Where to refill my bottle in India?

How are circuits which use complex ICs normally simulated?

Why can Shazam do this?

Manuscript was "unsubmitted" because the manuscript was deposited in Arxiv Preprints

Realistic Alternatives to Dust: What Else Could Feed a Plankton Bloom?

Why don't Unix/Linux systems traverse through directories until they find the required version of a linked library?

Lethal sonic weapons

Dual Citizen. Exited the US on Italian passport recently

Does light intensity oscillate really fast since it is a wave?

How come people say “Would of”?

Is it possible for the two major parties in the UK to form a coalition with each other instead of a much smaller party?

Deadlock Graph and Interpretation, solution to avoid

Is three citations per paragraph excessive for undergraduate research paper?

Unbreakable Formation vs. Cry of the Carnarium

Are USB sockets on wall outlets live all the time, even when the switch is off?

Monty Hall variation

Output the Arecibo Message

Does a dangling wire really electrocute me if I'm standing in water?

Springs with some finite mass

What is the steepest angle that a canal can be traversable without locks?

Is there a name of the flying bionic bird?

Inflated grade on resume at previous job, might former employer tell new employer?



Products and the axiom of choice



The 2019 Stack Overflow Developer Survey Results Are InUniversal property of the direct product, proof verificationDoes the existence of products in the category of sets imply the Axiom of Choice?Axiom of Choice and Cartesian ProductsConfusion regarding one formulation of the Axiom of Choice.Axiom of Choice (Naive Set Theory, Halmos)Do we need Axiom of Choice to make infinite choices from a set?Why do we need the axiom of choice in showing the non-emptiness of an infinite Cartesian productDefining relations without axiom of choiceProb. 9, Sec. 19 in Munkres' TOPOLOGY, 2nd edition: Equivalence of the choice axiom and non-emptyness of Cartesian productSimple question: Which is the Wikipedia definition of axiom of choiceAxiom of Choice iff Every set has a choice function










0












$begingroup$


Here: Universal property of the direct product, proof verification



Matematleta noted in the comments, that the definition of the product uses the axiom of choice by default.
Why is that?



The definition i am looking at is simply:



For sets $X_1, X_2, dotso, X_n$ is $prod_i= 1^n X_i:=(x_1,dotso, x_n)$



Analogously for an arbitrary index set.



Also I always wondered, why you need the axiom of choice to state, that the product of not empty sets is not empty.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Let $X$ be a set. Then look at $prod_AinmathcalP(X)setminusemptysetA$. This product is not empty is exactly saying "there exists a choice function"
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 23 at 2:46















0












$begingroup$


Here: Universal property of the direct product, proof verification



Matematleta noted in the comments, that the definition of the product uses the axiom of choice by default.
Why is that?



The definition i am looking at is simply:



For sets $X_1, X_2, dotso, X_n$ is $prod_i= 1^n X_i:=(x_1,dotso, x_n)$



Analogously for an arbitrary index set.



Also I always wondered, why you need the axiom of choice to state, that the product of not empty sets is not empty.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Let $X$ be a set. Then look at $prod_AinmathcalP(X)setminusemptysetA$. This product is not empty is exactly saying "there exists a choice function"
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 23 at 2:46













0












0








0


1



$begingroup$


Here: Universal property of the direct product, proof verification



Matematleta noted in the comments, that the definition of the product uses the axiom of choice by default.
Why is that?



The definition i am looking at is simply:



For sets $X_1, X_2, dotso, X_n$ is $prod_i= 1^n X_i:=(x_1,dotso, x_n)$



Analogously for an arbitrary index set.



Also I always wondered, why you need the axiom of choice to state, that the product of not empty sets is not empty.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




Here: Universal property of the direct product, proof verification



Matematleta noted in the comments, that the definition of the product uses the axiom of choice by default.
Why is that?



The definition i am looking at is simply:



For sets $X_1, X_2, dotso, X_n$ is $prod_i= 1^n X_i:=(x_1,dotso, x_n)$



Analogously for an arbitrary index set.



Also I always wondered, why you need the axiom of choice to state, that the product of not empty sets is not empty.







elementary-set-theory set-theory definition axiom-of-choice






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Mar 23 at 2:41









CornmanCornman

3,40321229




3,40321229







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Let $X$ be a set. Then look at $prod_AinmathcalP(X)setminusemptysetA$. This product is not empty is exactly saying "there exists a choice function"
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 23 at 2:46












  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Let $X$ be a set. Then look at $prod_AinmathcalP(X)setminusemptysetA$. This product is not empty is exactly saying "there exists a choice function"
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 23 at 2:46







1




1




$begingroup$
Let $X$ be a set. Then look at $prod_AinmathcalP(X)setminusemptysetA$. This product is not empty is exactly saying "there exists a choice function"
$endgroup$
– Holo
Mar 23 at 2:46




$begingroup$
Let $X$ be a set. Then look at $prod_AinmathcalP(X)setminusemptysetA$. This product is not empty is exactly saying "there exists a choice function"
$endgroup$
– Holo
Mar 23 at 2:46










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















4












$begingroup$

Because that's not a definition: what precisely is "$(x_1,...,x_n)$"? We might be tempted to hand-wave this away, and certainly nothing too surprising happens with finite tuples, but this is clearly unsatisfactory for arbitrary products - for example, what if I'm taking the product of a family of sets which isn't even linearly ordered in the first place?



  • In general, never be satisfied when a definition you've written has all the "hard work" being done by the word "analogously" or something similar.

So we have to rigorously define what we mean by "large" ordered tuples.



Intuitively, an element of $prod_iin IX_i$ should be an "$I$-ary sequence" whose $i$th term comes from $X_i$. The simplest way to make this precise is to think of sequences as just being nicely-dressed functions - the sequence "First term $0$, second term $1$, third term $0$" is just the function with domain $1,2,3$ sending $1$ to $0$, $2$ to $1$, and $3$ to $0$.



Abstractly, then, we're talking about the following




An element of $prod_iin IX_i$ is a function $p:Irightarrowbigcup_iin I X_i$ with $p(i)in X_i$ for each $iin I$.




Now to talk about functions it suffices to talk about ordered pairs, which we can do by e.g. Kuratowski's definition. So we've converted a single "ordered $I$-tuple" into a set of ordered pairs.



That explains where the definition comes from. And with this in mind it's clear that the nonemptiness of the product of nonempty sets is equivalent to the axiom of choice: a choice function for a family of disjoint nonempty sets is literally an element of the product of that family of sets!






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Thanks for this answer. Very clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Cornman
    Mar 23 at 2:55











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);













draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3158895%2fproducts-and-the-axiom-of-choice%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









4












$begingroup$

Because that's not a definition: what precisely is "$(x_1,...,x_n)$"? We might be tempted to hand-wave this away, and certainly nothing too surprising happens with finite tuples, but this is clearly unsatisfactory for arbitrary products - for example, what if I'm taking the product of a family of sets which isn't even linearly ordered in the first place?



  • In general, never be satisfied when a definition you've written has all the "hard work" being done by the word "analogously" or something similar.

So we have to rigorously define what we mean by "large" ordered tuples.



Intuitively, an element of $prod_iin IX_i$ should be an "$I$-ary sequence" whose $i$th term comes from $X_i$. The simplest way to make this precise is to think of sequences as just being nicely-dressed functions - the sequence "First term $0$, second term $1$, third term $0$" is just the function with domain $1,2,3$ sending $1$ to $0$, $2$ to $1$, and $3$ to $0$.



Abstractly, then, we're talking about the following




An element of $prod_iin IX_i$ is a function $p:Irightarrowbigcup_iin I X_i$ with $p(i)in X_i$ for each $iin I$.




Now to talk about functions it suffices to talk about ordered pairs, which we can do by e.g. Kuratowski's definition. So we've converted a single "ordered $I$-tuple" into a set of ordered pairs.



That explains where the definition comes from. And with this in mind it's clear that the nonemptiness of the product of nonempty sets is equivalent to the axiom of choice: a choice function for a family of disjoint nonempty sets is literally an element of the product of that family of sets!






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Thanks for this answer. Very clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Cornman
    Mar 23 at 2:55















4












$begingroup$

Because that's not a definition: what precisely is "$(x_1,...,x_n)$"? We might be tempted to hand-wave this away, and certainly nothing too surprising happens with finite tuples, but this is clearly unsatisfactory for arbitrary products - for example, what if I'm taking the product of a family of sets which isn't even linearly ordered in the first place?



  • In general, never be satisfied when a definition you've written has all the "hard work" being done by the word "analogously" or something similar.

So we have to rigorously define what we mean by "large" ordered tuples.



Intuitively, an element of $prod_iin IX_i$ should be an "$I$-ary sequence" whose $i$th term comes from $X_i$. The simplest way to make this precise is to think of sequences as just being nicely-dressed functions - the sequence "First term $0$, second term $1$, third term $0$" is just the function with domain $1,2,3$ sending $1$ to $0$, $2$ to $1$, and $3$ to $0$.



Abstractly, then, we're talking about the following




An element of $prod_iin IX_i$ is a function $p:Irightarrowbigcup_iin I X_i$ with $p(i)in X_i$ for each $iin I$.




Now to talk about functions it suffices to talk about ordered pairs, which we can do by e.g. Kuratowski's definition. So we've converted a single "ordered $I$-tuple" into a set of ordered pairs.



That explains where the definition comes from. And with this in mind it's clear that the nonemptiness of the product of nonempty sets is equivalent to the axiom of choice: a choice function for a family of disjoint nonempty sets is literally an element of the product of that family of sets!






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Thanks for this answer. Very clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Cornman
    Mar 23 at 2:55













4












4








4





$begingroup$

Because that's not a definition: what precisely is "$(x_1,...,x_n)$"? We might be tempted to hand-wave this away, and certainly nothing too surprising happens with finite tuples, but this is clearly unsatisfactory for arbitrary products - for example, what if I'm taking the product of a family of sets which isn't even linearly ordered in the first place?



  • In general, never be satisfied when a definition you've written has all the "hard work" being done by the word "analogously" or something similar.

So we have to rigorously define what we mean by "large" ordered tuples.



Intuitively, an element of $prod_iin IX_i$ should be an "$I$-ary sequence" whose $i$th term comes from $X_i$. The simplest way to make this precise is to think of sequences as just being nicely-dressed functions - the sequence "First term $0$, second term $1$, third term $0$" is just the function with domain $1,2,3$ sending $1$ to $0$, $2$ to $1$, and $3$ to $0$.



Abstractly, then, we're talking about the following




An element of $prod_iin IX_i$ is a function $p:Irightarrowbigcup_iin I X_i$ with $p(i)in X_i$ for each $iin I$.




Now to talk about functions it suffices to talk about ordered pairs, which we can do by e.g. Kuratowski's definition. So we've converted a single "ordered $I$-tuple" into a set of ordered pairs.



That explains where the definition comes from. And with this in mind it's clear that the nonemptiness of the product of nonempty sets is equivalent to the axiom of choice: a choice function for a family of disjoint nonempty sets is literally an element of the product of that family of sets!






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



Because that's not a definition: what precisely is "$(x_1,...,x_n)$"? We might be tempted to hand-wave this away, and certainly nothing too surprising happens with finite tuples, but this is clearly unsatisfactory for arbitrary products - for example, what if I'm taking the product of a family of sets which isn't even linearly ordered in the first place?



  • In general, never be satisfied when a definition you've written has all the "hard work" being done by the word "analogously" or something similar.

So we have to rigorously define what we mean by "large" ordered tuples.



Intuitively, an element of $prod_iin IX_i$ should be an "$I$-ary sequence" whose $i$th term comes from $X_i$. The simplest way to make this precise is to think of sequences as just being nicely-dressed functions - the sequence "First term $0$, second term $1$, third term $0$" is just the function with domain $1,2,3$ sending $1$ to $0$, $2$ to $1$, and $3$ to $0$.



Abstractly, then, we're talking about the following




An element of $prod_iin IX_i$ is a function $p:Irightarrowbigcup_iin I X_i$ with $p(i)in X_i$ for each $iin I$.




Now to talk about functions it suffices to talk about ordered pairs, which we can do by e.g. Kuratowski's definition. So we've converted a single "ordered $I$-tuple" into a set of ordered pairs.



That explains where the definition comes from. And with this in mind it's clear that the nonemptiness of the product of nonempty sets is equivalent to the axiom of choice: a choice function for a family of disjoint nonempty sets is literally an element of the product of that family of sets!







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered Mar 23 at 2:52









Noah SchweberNoah Schweber

128k10152294




128k10152294











  • $begingroup$
    Thanks for this answer. Very clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Cornman
    Mar 23 at 2:55
















  • $begingroup$
    Thanks for this answer. Very clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Cornman
    Mar 23 at 2:55















$begingroup$
Thanks for this answer. Very clear.
$endgroup$
– Cornman
Mar 23 at 2:55




$begingroup$
Thanks for this answer. Very clear.
$endgroup$
– Cornman
Mar 23 at 2:55

















draft saved

draft discarded
















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid


  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3158895%2fproducts-and-the-axiom-of-choice%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Solar Wings Breeze Design and development Specifications (Breeze) References Navigation menu1368-485X"Hang glider: Breeze (Solar Wings)"e

Kathakali Contents Etymology and nomenclature History Repertoire Songs and musical instruments Traditional plays Styles: Sampradayam Training centers and awards Relationship to other dance forms See also Notes References External links Navigation menueThe Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism: A-MSouth Asian Folklore: An EncyclopediaRoutledge International Encyclopedia of Women: Global Women's Issues and KnowledgeKathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to PlayKathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to PlayKathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to Play10.1353/atj.2005.0004The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism: A-MEncyclopedia of HinduismKathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to PlaySonic Liturgy: Ritual and Music in Hindu Tradition"The Mirror of Gesture"Kathakali Dance-drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to Play"Kathakali"Indian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceMedieval Indian Literature: An AnthologyThe Oxford Companion to Indian TheatreSouth Asian Folklore: An Encyclopedia : Afghanistan, Bangladesh, India, Nepal, Pakistan, Sri LankaThe Rise of Performance Studies: Rethinking Richard Schechner's Broad SpectrumIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceModern Asian Theatre and Performance 1900-2000Critical Theory and PerformanceBetween Theater and AnthropologyKathakali603847011Indian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceIndian Theatre: Traditions of PerformanceBetween Theater and AnthropologyBetween Theater and AnthropologyNambeesan Smaraka AwardsArchivedThe Cambridge Guide to TheatreRoutledge International Encyclopedia of Women: Global Women's Issues and KnowledgeThe Garland Encyclopedia of World Music: South Asia : the Indian subcontinentThe Ethos of Noh: Actors and Their Art10.2307/1145740By Means of Performance: Intercultural Studies of Theatre and Ritual10.1017/s204912550000100xReconceiving the Renaissance: A Critical ReaderPerformance TheoryListening to Theatre: The Aural Dimension of Beijing Opera10.2307/1146013Kathakali: The Art of the Non-WorldlyOn KathakaliKathakali, the dance theatreThe Kathakali Complex: Performance & StructureKathakali Dance-Drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to Play10.1093/obo/9780195399318-0071Drama and Ritual of Early Hinduism"In the Shadow of Hollywood Orientalism: Authentic East Indian Dancing"10.1080/08949460490274013Sanskrit Play Production in Ancient IndiaIndian Music: History and StructureBharata, the Nāṭyaśāstra233639306Table of Contents2238067286469807Dance In Indian Painting10.2307/32047833204783Kathakali Dance-Theatre: A Visual Narrative of Sacred Indian MimeIndian Classical Dance: The Renaissance and BeyondKathakali: an indigenous art-form of Keralaeee

Method to test if a number is a perfect power? Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern)Detecting perfect squares faster than by extracting square rooteffective way to get the integer sequence A181392 from oeisA rarely mentioned fact about perfect powersHow many numbers such $n$ are there that $n<100,lfloorsqrtn rfloor mid n$Check perfect squareness by modulo division against multiple basesFor what pair of integers $(a,b)$ is $3^a + 7^b$ a perfect square.Do there exist any positive integers $n$ such that $lfloore^nrfloor$ is a perfect power? What is the probability that one exists?finding perfect power factors of an integerProve that the sequence contains a perfect square for any natural number $m $ in the domain of $f$ .Counting Perfect Powers