Looking for Cantor's original proof of the Cantor-Bernstein theorem that relies on the axiom of choice?Schroder-Bernstein Theorem using ACCantor-Bernstein-like theorem: If $fcolon Ato B$ is injection and $gcolon Ato B$ is surjective, can we prove there is a bijection as well?Problem in Cardinality and OrderFoundation for analysis without axiom of choice?Lemma required for Cantor-Bernstein-Schroeder TheoremHall's theorem vs Axiom of Choice?Do you need the Axiom of Choice to accept Cantor's Diagonal Proof?Proof ultrafilter theorem without axiom of choice?Relative Consistency proof for the Axiom of ChoiceBernstein sets, Well-Ordering theorem vs Axiom of ChoiceDoes this version of Schröder-Bernstein-Cantor imply choice?How find a counterexample that Axiom of dependent choice implies the Axiom of choice?Where does this proof of the Continuum Hypothesis use the axiom of choice?

When were female captains banned from Starfleet?

Why does the Sun have different day lengths, but not the gas giants?

What to do when eye contact makes your coworker uncomfortable?

Shouldn’t conservatives embrace universal basic income?

How do I tell my boss that I'm quitting soon, especially given that a colleague just left this week

Why is so much work done on numerical verification of the Riemann Hypothesis?

How to get directions in deep space?

What (the heck) is a Super Worm Equinox Moon?

What's the name of the logical fallacy where a debater extends a statement far beyond the original statement to make it true?

Has any country ever had 2 former presidents in jail simultaneously?

What features enable the Su-25 Frogfoot to operate with such a wide variety of fuels?

"It doesn't matter" or "it won't matter"?

Is there a RAID 0 Equivalent for RAM?

What does "Scientists rise up against statistical significance" mean? (Comment in Nature)

Does the reader need to like the PoV character?

Is there any evidence that Cleopatra and Caesarion considered fleeing to India to escape the Romans?

Why should universal income be universal?

The IT department bottlenecks progress, how should I handle this?

It grows, but water kills it

Why is the "ls" command showing permissions of files in a FAT32 partition?

C++ copy constructor called at return

How could a planet have erratic days?

How do I fix the group tension caused by my character stealing and possibly killing without provocation?

Short story about a deaf man, who cuts people tongues



Looking for Cantor's original proof of the Cantor-Bernstein theorem that relies on the axiom of choice?


Schroder-Bernstein Theorem using ACCantor-Bernstein-like theorem: If $fcolon Ato B$ is injection and $gcolon Ato B$ is surjective, can we prove there is a bijection as well?Problem in Cardinality and OrderFoundation for analysis without axiom of choice?Lemma required for Cantor-Bernstein-Schroeder TheoremHall's theorem vs Axiom of Choice?Do you need the Axiom of Choice to accept Cantor's Diagonal Proof?Proof ultrafilter theorem without axiom of choice?Relative Consistency proof for the Axiom of ChoiceBernstein sets, Well-Ordering theorem vs Axiom of ChoiceDoes this version of Schröder-Bernstein-Cantor imply choice?How find a counterexample that Axiom of dependent choice implies the Axiom of choice?Where does this proof of the Continuum Hypothesis use the axiom of choice?













2












$begingroup$


Even a sketch of it would be good enough. Thanks.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    Are you familiar with ordinals and well-orders?
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:15










  • $begingroup$
    @MichaelGreinecker I am, yes.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:20















2












$begingroup$


Even a sketch of it would be good enough. Thanks.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    Are you familiar with ordinals and well-orders?
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:15










  • $begingroup$
    @MichaelGreinecker I am, yes.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:20













2












2








2


1



$begingroup$


Even a sketch of it would be good enough. Thanks.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




Even a sketch of it would be good enough. Thanks.







set-theory cardinals axiom-of-choice






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Oct 29 '12 at 17:11









Asaf Karagila

306k33438769




306k33438769










asked Oct 29 '12 at 16:05









Acid2Acid2

334213




334213











  • $begingroup$
    Are you familiar with ordinals and well-orders?
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:15










  • $begingroup$
    @MichaelGreinecker I am, yes.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:20
















  • $begingroup$
    Are you familiar with ordinals and well-orders?
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:15










  • $begingroup$
    @MichaelGreinecker I am, yes.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:20















$begingroup$
Are you familiar with ordinals and well-orders?
$endgroup$
– Michael Greinecker
Oct 29 '12 at 16:15




$begingroup$
Are you familiar with ordinals and well-orders?
$endgroup$
– Michael Greinecker
Oct 29 '12 at 16:15












$begingroup$
@MichaelGreinecker I am, yes.
$endgroup$
– Acid2
Oct 29 '12 at 16:20




$begingroup$
@MichaelGreinecker I am, yes.
$endgroup$
– Acid2
Oct 29 '12 at 16:20










4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes


















9












$begingroup$

The proof relies on the well-ordering principle: Any set is well-orderable. Since any two well-orderings are comparable, this gives the result.



Cantor was not sure for many years whether this principle was self-evidently true, needed a proof, or needed to be postulated, so his writings oscillate between claiming the result as true, or as needing a proof.



Cantor first considered the statement (that he called the equivalence theorem) around 1882, in the form:




If $Asubseteq Bsubseteq C$ and $Asim C$, then $Asim B$,




where $Asim B$ means that there is a bijection between $A$ and $B$. Originally, this was stated only for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and assuming $mathsfCH$, the continuum hypothesis. A proof in this setting appeared in 1883, see page 574 of



  • Georg Cantor. Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten. V, Math. Ann.
    21 (4), (1883), 545–590. MR1510215

In full generality, the theorem is explicitly stated in the first half of a two-part paper published in Mathematische Annalen in 1895 and 1897, the English translation is




  • Contributions to the founding of the theory of transfinite
    numbers
    , translated, and provided with an introduction and notes, by Philip
    E. B. Jourdain. Dover Publications, Inc., New York, N. Y., 1952. MR0045635
    (13,612d)

It appears as Theorem B, page 91, (Satze B, page 484, in the 1895 paper):




B. If two aggregates $M$ and $N$ are such that $M$ is equivalent to a part $N_1$ of $N$ and $N$ to a part $M_1$ of $M$, then $M$ and $N$ are equivalent.



B. Sind zwei Mengen $M$ und $N$ so beschaffen, dass $M$ mit einem Theil $N_1$ von
$N$ und $N$ mit einem Theil $M_1$ von $M$ äquivalent ist, so sind auch $M$ und $N$
äquivalent.




As I mentioned above, he intended to derive the result from trichotomy (any two cardinals are comparable), which renders the statement trivial by modern standards. In more detail: Cantor expected all sets to be well-orderable. Any two well-orders are comparable, in fact, if $alpha$ and $beta$ are well-orders, then exactly one of the following holds:



  1. $alpha$ and $beta$ are order isomorphic, and the isomorphism is unique.

  2. $alpha$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $beta$, and the isomorphism is unique.

  3. $beta$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $alpha$, and the isomorphism is unique.

Given $A$, there is a well-order of smallest possible length that is in bijection with $A$ (assuming that $A$ is well-orderable). Similarly for $B$. If $A$ and $B$ inject into each other, the trichotomy above easily gives us that the corresponding ordinals are order isomorphic, so that $Asim B$.



Details were postponed to the second part of his paper, where the theory of ordinals is developed, and were not presented in full. Whether he actually had a complete proof is questioned by some authors, see for example De Araujo. As pointed out above, the issue is that at that time, it was not clear whether Cantor considered trichotomy and other
versions of choice as statements that ought to be proved from earlier principles, or as additional assumptions. This may explain why Cantor's early mentions of the theorem regard it as an open question, both in papers (1884) and in his correspondence with Dedekind (1883).




All this comes from a book I am writing. A nice alternative source is




Gregory H. Moore. Zermelo’s axiom of choice. Its origins, development, and influence, Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences 8, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1982. MR0679315 (85b:01036)







share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Thank you for your answer as well. Reading about how these ideas were historically developed is quite interesting. Is that what your book's going to be about?
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:46










  • $begingroup$
    It is about a few selected topics in set theory, but I've tried to pay attention to historical details when appropriate. The Schroeder-Bernstein theorem is particularly interesting from a historical point of view.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:53










  • $begingroup$
    @Andres Dedekind essentially prove the theorem in 1887. The corresponding part in his Gesammelte Werke can be found here.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 30 '12 at 23:50










  • $begingroup$
    Yes, Michael, thanks. I only wrote above on the part that was strictly related to Cantor, I discuss the history a bit more in the book.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Oct 31 '12 at 1:39






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    How's the book coming along? Would be interested to read it.
    $endgroup$
    – David Roberts
    Jun 30 '17 at 7:33


















3












$begingroup$

Using the axiom of choice, every set can be well ordered. For each set $X$, let $|X|$ be the smallest ordinal order-isomorphic to some well-ordering of $X$. If there is an injection $f:Yto X$, then $Y$ can be identified with a subset of $X$ and hence with a subset of $|X|$. The order type of this set is smaller or equal to $|X|$, hence $|Y|leq |X|$. If there is also an injection from $X$ to $Y$, we can conclude that $|X|leq|Y|$. Since the class of ordinals is well-ordered it satisfies anti-symmetry and we can conclude that $|X|=|Y|$. So there are bijections from both $X$ and $Y$ to the ordinal $|X|=|Y|$, and combining these bijections gives us a bijection between $X$ and $Y$.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Wow that was easy - easier than I expected! Thanks for your help.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:34










  • $begingroup$
    One question; why isn't this proof more 'popular'? There are various different proofs of this theorem and even the simplest of those (two) that I've been able to follow/understand are quite complicated and not much fun.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:40










  • $begingroup$
    It is a fundamental result of cardinal arithmetic that works without the axiom of choice and can be used before one learns about well-orders. A way the usual proofs can be made less messy is by assuming one set is a subset of the other and the injection into the bigger set is the identity.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:43










  • $begingroup$
    Doesn't the fact that all cardinals are comparable depend on the axiom of choice? How can this proof work, as you say, without it?
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:52










  • $begingroup$
    I mean the usual Cantor-Bernstein theorem and proofs by back-and-forth or a fixed point argument. Te proof I've given depends of course on the axiom of choice.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:55


















3












$begingroup$

Check http://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-0348-0224-6/page/1



The details are quite different from those in the other answers here.



To complete my answer:



Cantor's original proof of the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem.



First, let me comment on some of the points mentioned above.



  1. The question assumes that Cantor's original proof relied on the axiom of choice. But the axiom of choice emerged only in 1904, well after Cantor finished his research.


  2. Cantor mentioned the well-ordering principle only in his 1883 paper (the above referenced Über unendlich… paper). So it cannot be maintained that his view on the principle "oscillated".


  3. Cantor needed the well-ordering principle in order to establish the arithmetic operations between his transfinite numbers (which he later called ordinals), and not for trichotomy, which is not mentioned in 1883. With the well-ordering principle Cantor also tacitly assumed a numbering principle which provides that for every well-ordered set there is a transfinite number similar to it, which is thus its numbering (Anzahl). With his later definition of the transfinite numbers (ordinals) by abstraction, instead of the earlier generation principles, Cantor had no further need for the well-ordering principle and its ancillary numbering principle to provide for the arithmetic operations between ordinals. So Cantor dropped the well-ordering principle after 1883.


  4. Cantor stated the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem (CBT) in 1883 as an immediate corollary to several theorems that established that the second number-class. Thus CBT was established for sets of the power $aleph_1$, not for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and without assuming CH. CH is needed to apply the theorem to subsets of $mathbb R^n$ but Cantor never did that. In fact, he didn't have to for, I believe, Cantor had a direct proof for CBT for $mathbb R$ and thus for $mathbb R^n$ (in view of his results in 1878). See my book referenced above.


  5. Cantor's construction of the number-classes from 1883 can be generalized. The proof is by transfinite induction which Cantor used for other proofs as well without identifying the procedure explicitly. Note that there are in fact two inductive arguments in the proof: one over the index of the number-classes and a second over the numbers in every preceding number-class. The generalized CBT is a necessary lemma in the proof establishing the construction of the scale of number-classes. Again I must reference my book.


  6. In the referenced 1895 paper three versions of CBT appear: the quoted B, the version which was mentioned in the answer above as originating from 1882, and a third version denoted there E.


  7. Cantor presented all three versions as simple corollary to the theorem referenced above as trichotomy. There Cantor postponed the proof of trichotomy to until such time when the ascending sequence of cardinal numbers will be established. The ground work for that scale, namely the scale of the number-classes was established in the 1897 paper. However, Cantor did not go back to trichotomy and this created some confusion. Zermelo interpreted the situation as implying that Cantor could not prove trichotomy and his view was adopted by almost all commentators on Cantor.


  8. Cantor intended to publish a third sequel to the 1895, 1897 papers. We know that from his correspondence with Hilbert. There he presumably intended to fill the blanks he left around the trichotomy theorem. However, Cantor was hesitant to go ahead with the third sequel until he got Dedekind's approval to the ideas contained therein, but Dedekind refused to get involved. We know this again from Cantor's correspondence. The ideas which Cantor was afraid to publish were two: First, that there are inconsistent sets in mathematics. These are the classes of today. Had Cantor published his ideas, which may have originated already in 1883, perhaps the scare of the antinomies would have been avoided. Second, that a new axiom is necessary to introduce to mathematics. It was the statement presented as corollary D to trichotomy. In fact Cantor was ready to assume both D and CBT (corollary B) but fortunately proofs for CBT began to emerge in 1897 and so there was no need to take CBT as axiom. These axioms were hinted in a letter to Schoenflies of 1899.


  9. In light of the above it seems to me that the idea that Cantor presented CBT in 1895 as an open problem cannot be maintained. Notwithstanding this remark I do recommend that you should consult besides my book also Ferreiros 1999, Birkhäuser.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Link only answers are not really good; could you at least give a sketch of the argument?
    $endgroup$
    – egreg
    Feb 15 '14 at 18:28










  • $begingroup$
    Nice reference, I was not aware of it. Thanks!
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Feb 16 '14 at 8:16










  • $begingroup$
    One thing about the fact that Cantor's proof relied on the axiom of choice; note that in fact many proofs given before the foundational crisis of the late-19th and early-20th centuries were using certain axioms before these were formulated. Because mathematicians didn't really think in terms of axioms (many still don't) and formal definitions; but when that began, the proofs were analyzed and in some of them we found use of the axiom of choice (or other axioms), and in others we didn't. If a proof uses the axiom of choice, then it uses the axiom of choice. Regardless to its temporal origins.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '14 at 17:14










  • $begingroup$
    Dear Arie, Many thanks for the expanded remarks.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    May 9 '14 at 22:48


















2












$begingroup$

Cantor's original proof relies on the well-ordering principle, stating that every set can be well-ordered.



If $Aleq B$, namely there is an injection from $A$ into $B$; and $Bleq A$, so there is also an injection from $B$ into $A$, using the well-ordering principle let $alpha$ be the least ordinal such that $alpha$ has a bijection with $A$; and let $beta$ be the least ordinal which has a bijection with $B$.



Now note that a subset of an ordinal can be "collapsed" and be put in bijection with an ordinal, not necessarily a smaller one though. If $gamma<alpha$ was such that there was an injection from $A$ into $gamma$ then by collapsing the range of this injection we would get a bijection of $A$ with an ordinal $leqgamma$. Therefore $A$ cannot be injected into any smaller ordinal than $alpha$ or we would contradict the minimality of $alpha$, and the same argument shows that $B$ cannot be injected into any ordinal smaller than $beta$.



By composing the injections between $A$ and $B$, and the bijections with $alpha$ and $beta$ we have an injection from $A$ into $beta$ and from $B$ into $alpha$. The above argument shows that we have $alphaleqbeta$ as well $betaleqalpha$. Therefore we must have $alpha=beta$.



By composing the bijections from $A$ to $alpha$ and from $alpha$ to $B$ we have a bijection between $A$ and $B$ as wanted.



See also: Cantor-Bernstein-like theorem: If $fcolon Ato B$ is injection and $gcolon Ato B$ is surjective, can we prove there is a bijection as well?






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$












    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    );
    );
    , "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function()
    var channelOptions =
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    ;
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
    createEditor();
    );

    else
    createEditor();

    );

    function createEditor()
    StackExchange.prepareEditor(
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader:
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    ,
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    );



    );













    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function ()
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f223587%2flooking-for-cantors-original-proof-of-the-cantor-bernstein-theorem-that-relies%23new-answer', 'question_page');

    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    4 Answers
    4






    active

    oldest

    votes








    4 Answers
    4






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    9












    $begingroup$

    The proof relies on the well-ordering principle: Any set is well-orderable. Since any two well-orderings are comparable, this gives the result.



    Cantor was not sure for many years whether this principle was self-evidently true, needed a proof, or needed to be postulated, so his writings oscillate between claiming the result as true, or as needing a proof.



    Cantor first considered the statement (that he called the equivalence theorem) around 1882, in the form:




    If $Asubseteq Bsubseteq C$ and $Asim C$, then $Asim B$,




    where $Asim B$ means that there is a bijection between $A$ and $B$. Originally, this was stated only for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and assuming $mathsfCH$, the continuum hypothesis. A proof in this setting appeared in 1883, see page 574 of



    • Georg Cantor. Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten. V, Math. Ann.
      21 (4), (1883), 545–590. MR1510215

    In full generality, the theorem is explicitly stated in the first half of a two-part paper published in Mathematische Annalen in 1895 and 1897, the English translation is




    • Contributions to the founding of the theory of transfinite
      numbers
      , translated, and provided with an introduction and notes, by Philip
      E. B. Jourdain. Dover Publications, Inc., New York, N. Y., 1952. MR0045635
      (13,612d)

    It appears as Theorem B, page 91, (Satze B, page 484, in the 1895 paper):




    B. If two aggregates $M$ and $N$ are such that $M$ is equivalent to a part $N_1$ of $N$ and $N$ to a part $M_1$ of $M$, then $M$ and $N$ are equivalent.



    B. Sind zwei Mengen $M$ und $N$ so beschaffen, dass $M$ mit einem Theil $N_1$ von
    $N$ und $N$ mit einem Theil $M_1$ von $M$ äquivalent ist, so sind auch $M$ und $N$
    äquivalent.




    As I mentioned above, he intended to derive the result from trichotomy (any two cardinals are comparable), which renders the statement trivial by modern standards. In more detail: Cantor expected all sets to be well-orderable. Any two well-orders are comparable, in fact, if $alpha$ and $beta$ are well-orders, then exactly one of the following holds:



    1. $alpha$ and $beta$ are order isomorphic, and the isomorphism is unique.

    2. $alpha$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $beta$, and the isomorphism is unique.

    3. $beta$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $alpha$, and the isomorphism is unique.

    Given $A$, there is a well-order of smallest possible length that is in bijection with $A$ (assuming that $A$ is well-orderable). Similarly for $B$. If $A$ and $B$ inject into each other, the trichotomy above easily gives us that the corresponding ordinals are order isomorphic, so that $Asim B$.



    Details were postponed to the second part of his paper, where the theory of ordinals is developed, and were not presented in full. Whether he actually had a complete proof is questioned by some authors, see for example De Araujo. As pointed out above, the issue is that at that time, it was not clear whether Cantor considered trichotomy and other
    versions of choice as statements that ought to be proved from earlier principles, or as additional assumptions. This may explain why Cantor's early mentions of the theorem regard it as an open question, both in papers (1884) and in his correspondence with Dedekind (1883).




    All this comes from a book I am writing. A nice alternative source is




    Gregory H. Moore. Zermelo’s axiom of choice. Its origins, development, and influence, Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences 8, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1982. MR0679315 (85b:01036)







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      Thank you for your answer as well. Reading about how these ideas were historically developed is quite interesting. Is that what your book's going to be about?
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:46










    • $begingroup$
      It is about a few selected topics in set theory, but I've tried to pay attention to historical details when appropriate. The Schroeder-Bernstein theorem is particularly interesting from a historical point of view.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:53










    • $begingroup$
      @Andres Dedekind essentially prove the theorem in 1887. The corresponding part in his Gesammelte Werke can be found here.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 30 '12 at 23:50










    • $begingroup$
      Yes, Michael, thanks. I only wrote above on the part that was strictly related to Cantor, I discuss the history a bit more in the book.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Oct 31 '12 at 1:39






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      How's the book coming along? Would be interested to read it.
      $endgroup$
      – David Roberts
      Jun 30 '17 at 7:33















    9












    $begingroup$

    The proof relies on the well-ordering principle: Any set is well-orderable. Since any two well-orderings are comparable, this gives the result.



    Cantor was not sure for many years whether this principle was self-evidently true, needed a proof, or needed to be postulated, so his writings oscillate between claiming the result as true, or as needing a proof.



    Cantor first considered the statement (that he called the equivalence theorem) around 1882, in the form:




    If $Asubseteq Bsubseteq C$ and $Asim C$, then $Asim B$,




    where $Asim B$ means that there is a bijection between $A$ and $B$. Originally, this was stated only for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and assuming $mathsfCH$, the continuum hypothesis. A proof in this setting appeared in 1883, see page 574 of



    • Georg Cantor. Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten. V, Math. Ann.
      21 (4), (1883), 545–590. MR1510215

    In full generality, the theorem is explicitly stated in the first half of a two-part paper published in Mathematische Annalen in 1895 and 1897, the English translation is




    • Contributions to the founding of the theory of transfinite
      numbers
      , translated, and provided with an introduction and notes, by Philip
      E. B. Jourdain. Dover Publications, Inc., New York, N. Y., 1952. MR0045635
      (13,612d)

    It appears as Theorem B, page 91, (Satze B, page 484, in the 1895 paper):




    B. If two aggregates $M$ and $N$ are such that $M$ is equivalent to a part $N_1$ of $N$ and $N$ to a part $M_1$ of $M$, then $M$ and $N$ are equivalent.



    B. Sind zwei Mengen $M$ und $N$ so beschaffen, dass $M$ mit einem Theil $N_1$ von
    $N$ und $N$ mit einem Theil $M_1$ von $M$ äquivalent ist, so sind auch $M$ und $N$
    äquivalent.




    As I mentioned above, he intended to derive the result from trichotomy (any two cardinals are comparable), which renders the statement trivial by modern standards. In more detail: Cantor expected all sets to be well-orderable. Any two well-orders are comparable, in fact, if $alpha$ and $beta$ are well-orders, then exactly one of the following holds:



    1. $alpha$ and $beta$ are order isomorphic, and the isomorphism is unique.

    2. $alpha$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $beta$, and the isomorphism is unique.

    3. $beta$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $alpha$, and the isomorphism is unique.

    Given $A$, there is a well-order of smallest possible length that is in bijection with $A$ (assuming that $A$ is well-orderable). Similarly for $B$. If $A$ and $B$ inject into each other, the trichotomy above easily gives us that the corresponding ordinals are order isomorphic, so that $Asim B$.



    Details were postponed to the second part of his paper, where the theory of ordinals is developed, and were not presented in full. Whether he actually had a complete proof is questioned by some authors, see for example De Araujo. As pointed out above, the issue is that at that time, it was not clear whether Cantor considered trichotomy and other
    versions of choice as statements that ought to be proved from earlier principles, or as additional assumptions. This may explain why Cantor's early mentions of the theorem regard it as an open question, both in papers (1884) and in his correspondence with Dedekind (1883).




    All this comes from a book I am writing. A nice alternative source is




    Gregory H. Moore. Zermelo’s axiom of choice. Its origins, development, and influence, Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences 8, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1982. MR0679315 (85b:01036)







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      Thank you for your answer as well. Reading about how these ideas were historically developed is quite interesting. Is that what your book's going to be about?
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:46










    • $begingroup$
      It is about a few selected topics in set theory, but I've tried to pay attention to historical details when appropriate. The Schroeder-Bernstein theorem is particularly interesting from a historical point of view.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:53










    • $begingroup$
      @Andres Dedekind essentially prove the theorem in 1887. The corresponding part in his Gesammelte Werke can be found here.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 30 '12 at 23:50










    • $begingroup$
      Yes, Michael, thanks. I only wrote above on the part that was strictly related to Cantor, I discuss the history a bit more in the book.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Oct 31 '12 at 1:39






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      How's the book coming along? Would be interested to read it.
      $endgroup$
      – David Roberts
      Jun 30 '17 at 7:33













    9












    9








    9





    $begingroup$

    The proof relies on the well-ordering principle: Any set is well-orderable. Since any two well-orderings are comparable, this gives the result.



    Cantor was not sure for many years whether this principle was self-evidently true, needed a proof, or needed to be postulated, so his writings oscillate between claiming the result as true, or as needing a proof.



    Cantor first considered the statement (that he called the equivalence theorem) around 1882, in the form:




    If $Asubseteq Bsubseteq C$ and $Asim C$, then $Asim B$,




    where $Asim B$ means that there is a bijection between $A$ and $B$. Originally, this was stated only for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and assuming $mathsfCH$, the continuum hypothesis. A proof in this setting appeared in 1883, see page 574 of



    • Georg Cantor. Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten. V, Math. Ann.
      21 (4), (1883), 545–590. MR1510215

    In full generality, the theorem is explicitly stated in the first half of a two-part paper published in Mathematische Annalen in 1895 and 1897, the English translation is




    • Contributions to the founding of the theory of transfinite
      numbers
      , translated, and provided with an introduction and notes, by Philip
      E. B. Jourdain. Dover Publications, Inc., New York, N. Y., 1952. MR0045635
      (13,612d)

    It appears as Theorem B, page 91, (Satze B, page 484, in the 1895 paper):




    B. If two aggregates $M$ and $N$ are such that $M$ is equivalent to a part $N_1$ of $N$ and $N$ to a part $M_1$ of $M$, then $M$ and $N$ are equivalent.



    B. Sind zwei Mengen $M$ und $N$ so beschaffen, dass $M$ mit einem Theil $N_1$ von
    $N$ und $N$ mit einem Theil $M_1$ von $M$ äquivalent ist, so sind auch $M$ und $N$
    äquivalent.




    As I mentioned above, he intended to derive the result from trichotomy (any two cardinals are comparable), which renders the statement trivial by modern standards. In more detail: Cantor expected all sets to be well-orderable. Any two well-orders are comparable, in fact, if $alpha$ and $beta$ are well-orders, then exactly one of the following holds:



    1. $alpha$ and $beta$ are order isomorphic, and the isomorphism is unique.

    2. $alpha$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $beta$, and the isomorphism is unique.

    3. $beta$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $alpha$, and the isomorphism is unique.

    Given $A$, there is a well-order of smallest possible length that is in bijection with $A$ (assuming that $A$ is well-orderable). Similarly for $B$. If $A$ and $B$ inject into each other, the trichotomy above easily gives us that the corresponding ordinals are order isomorphic, so that $Asim B$.



    Details were postponed to the second part of his paper, where the theory of ordinals is developed, and were not presented in full. Whether he actually had a complete proof is questioned by some authors, see for example De Araujo. As pointed out above, the issue is that at that time, it was not clear whether Cantor considered trichotomy and other
    versions of choice as statements that ought to be proved from earlier principles, or as additional assumptions. This may explain why Cantor's early mentions of the theorem regard it as an open question, both in papers (1884) and in his correspondence with Dedekind (1883).




    All this comes from a book I am writing. A nice alternative source is




    Gregory H. Moore. Zermelo’s axiom of choice. Its origins, development, and influence, Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences 8, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1982. MR0679315 (85b:01036)







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    The proof relies on the well-ordering principle: Any set is well-orderable. Since any two well-orderings are comparable, this gives the result.



    Cantor was not sure for many years whether this principle was self-evidently true, needed a proof, or needed to be postulated, so his writings oscillate between claiming the result as true, or as needing a proof.



    Cantor first considered the statement (that he called the equivalence theorem) around 1882, in the form:




    If $Asubseteq Bsubseteq C$ and $Asim C$, then $Asim B$,




    where $Asim B$ means that there is a bijection between $A$ and $B$. Originally, this was stated only for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and assuming $mathsfCH$, the continuum hypothesis. A proof in this setting appeared in 1883, see page 574 of



    • Georg Cantor. Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten. V, Math. Ann.
      21 (4), (1883), 545–590. MR1510215

    In full generality, the theorem is explicitly stated in the first half of a two-part paper published in Mathematische Annalen in 1895 and 1897, the English translation is




    • Contributions to the founding of the theory of transfinite
      numbers
      , translated, and provided with an introduction and notes, by Philip
      E. B. Jourdain. Dover Publications, Inc., New York, N. Y., 1952. MR0045635
      (13,612d)

    It appears as Theorem B, page 91, (Satze B, page 484, in the 1895 paper):




    B. If two aggregates $M$ and $N$ are such that $M$ is equivalent to a part $N_1$ of $N$ and $N$ to a part $M_1$ of $M$, then $M$ and $N$ are equivalent.



    B. Sind zwei Mengen $M$ und $N$ so beschaffen, dass $M$ mit einem Theil $N_1$ von
    $N$ und $N$ mit einem Theil $M_1$ von $M$ äquivalent ist, so sind auch $M$ und $N$
    äquivalent.




    As I mentioned above, he intended to derive the result from trichotomy (any two cardinals are comparable), which renders the statement trivial by modern standards. In more detail: Cantor expected all sets to be well-orderable. Any two well-orders are comparable, in fact, if $alpha$ and $beta$ are well-orders, then exactly one of the following holds:



    1. $alpha$ and $beta$ are order isomorphic, and the isomorphism is unique.

    2. $alpha$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $beta$, and the isomorphism is unique.

    3. $beta$ is order isomorphic to a unique proper initial segment of $alpha$, and the isomorphism is unique.

    Given $A$, there is a well-order of smallest possible length that is in bijection with $A$ (assuming that $A$ is well-orderable). Similarly for $B$. If $A$ and $B$ inject into each other, the trichotomy above easily gives us that the corresponding ordinals are order isomorphic, so that $Asim B$.



    Details were postponed to the second part of his paper, where the theory of ordinals is developed, and were not presented in full. Whether he actually had a complete proof is questioned by some authors, see for example De Araujo. As pointed out above, the issue is that at that time, it was not clear whether Cantor considered trichotomy and other
    versions of choice as statements that ought to be proved from earlier principles, or as additional assumptions. This may explain why Cantor's early mentions of the theorem regard it as an open question, both in papers (1884) and in his correspondence with Dedekind (1883).




    All this comes from a book I am writing. A nice alternative source is




    Gregory H. Moore. Zermelo’s axiom of choice. Its origins, development, and influence, Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences 8, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1982. MR0679315 (85b:01036)








    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Oct 29 '12 at 16:55

























    answered Oct 29 '12 at 16:32









    Andrés E. CaicedoAndrés E. Caicedo

    65.8k8160251




    65.8k8160251











    • $begingroup$
      Thank you for your answer as well. Reading about how these ideas were historically developed is quite interesting. Is that what your book's going to be about?
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:46










    • $begingroup$
      It is about a few selected topics in set theory, but I've tried to pay attention to historical details when appropriate. The Schroeder-Bernstein theorem is particularly interesting from a historical point of view.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:53










    • $begingroup$
      @Andres Dedekind essentially prove the theorem in 1887. The corresponding part in his Gesammelte Werke can be found here.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 30 '12 at 23:50










    • $begingroup$
      Yes, Michael, thanks. I only wrote above on the part that was strictly related to Cantor, I discuss the history a bit more in the book.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Oct 31 '12 at 1:39






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      How's the book coming along? Would be interested to read it.
      $endgroup$
      – David Roberts
      Jun 30 '17 at 7:33
















    • $begingroup$
      Thank you for your answer as well. Reading about how these ideas were historically developed is quite interesting. Is that what your book's going to be about?
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:46










    • $begingroup$
      It is about a few selected topics in set theory, but I've tried to pay attention to historical details when appropriate. The Schroeder-Bernstein theorem is particularly interesting from a historical point of view.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:53










    • $begingroup$
      @Andres Dedekind essentially prove the theorem in 1887. The corresponding part in his Gesammelte Werke can be found here.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 30 '12 at 23:50










    • $begingroup$
      Yes, Michael, thanks. I only wrote above on the part that was strictly related to Cantor, I discuss the history a bit more in the book.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Oct 31 '12 at 1:39






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      How's the book coming along? Would be interested to read it.
      $endgroup$
      – David Roberts
      Jun 30 '17 at 7:33















    $begingroup$
    Thank you for your answer as well. Reading about how these ideas were historically developed is quite interesting. Is that what your book's going to be about?
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:46




    $begingroup$
    Thank you for your answer as well. Reading about how these ideas were historically developed is quite interesting. Is that what your book's going to be about?
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:46












    $begingroup$
    It is about a few selected topics in set theory, but I've tried to pay attention to historical details when appropriate. The Schroeder-Bernstein theorem is particularly interesting from a historical point of view.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:53




    $begingroup$
    It is about a few selected topics in set theory, but I've tried to pay attention to historical details when appropriate. The Schroeder-Bernstein theorem is particularly interesting from a historical point of view.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:53












    $begingroup$
    @Andres Dedekind essentially prove the theorem in 1887. The corresponding part in his Gesammelte Werke can be found here.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 30 '12 at 23:50




    $begingroup$
    @Andres Dedekind essentially prove the theorem in 1887. The corresponding part in his Gesammelte Werke can be found here.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 30 '12 at 23:50












    $begingroup$
    Yes, Michael, thanks. I only wrote above on the part that was strictly related to Cantor, I discuss the history a bit more in the book.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Oct 31 '12 at 1:39




    $begingroup$
    Yes, Michael, thanks. I only wrote above on the part that was strictly related to Cantor, I discuss the history a bit more in the book.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Oct 31 '12 at 1:39




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    How's the book coming along? Would be interested to read it.
    $endgroup$
    – David Roberts
    Jun 30 '17 at 7:33




    $begingroup$
    How's the book coming along? Would be interested to read it.
    $endgroup$
    – David Roberts
    Jun 30 '17 at 7:33











    3












    $begingroup$

    Using the axiom of choice, every set can be well ordered. For each set $X$, let $|X|$ be the smallest ordinal order-isomorphic to some well-ordering of $X$. If there is an injection $f:Yto X$, then $Y$ can be identified with a subset of $X$ and hence with a subset of $|X|$. The order type of this set is smaller or equal to $|X|$, hence $|Y|leq |X|$. If there is also an injection from $X$ to $Y$, we can conclude that $|X|leq|Y|$. Since the class of ordinals is well-ordered it satisfies anti-symmetry and we can conclude that $|X|=|Y|$. So there are bijections from both $X$ and $Y$ to the ordinal $|X|=|Y|$, and combining these bijections gives us a bijection between $X$ and $Y$.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      Wow that was easy - easier than I expected! Thanks for your help.
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:34










    • $begingroup$
      One question; why isn't this proof more 'popular'? There are various different proofs of this theorem and even the simplest of those (two) that I've been able to follow/understand are quite complicated and not much fun.
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:40










    • $begingroup$
      It is a fundamental result of cardinal arithmetic that works without the axiom of choice and can be used before one learns about well-orders. A way the usual proofs can be made less messy is by assuming one set is a subset of the other and the injection into the bigger set is the identity.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:43










    • $begingroup$
      Doesn't the fact that all cardinals are comparable depend on the axiom of choice? How can this proof work, as you say, without it?
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:52










    • $begingroup$
      I mean the usual Cantor-Bernstein theorem and proofs by back-and-forth or a fixed point argument. Te proof I've given depends of course on the axiom of choice.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:55















    3












    $begingroup$

    Using the axiom of choice, every set can be well ordered. For each set $X$, let $|X|$ be the smallest ordinal order-isomorphic to some well-ordering of $X$. If there is an injection $f:Yto X$, then $Y$ can be identified with a subset of $X$ and hence with a subset of $|X|$. The order type of this set is smaller or equal to $|X|$, hence $|Y|leq |X|$. If there is also an injection from $X$ to $Y$, we can conclude that $|X|leq|Y|$. Since the class of ordinals is well-ordered it satisfies anti-symmetry and we can conclude that $|X|=|Y|$. So there are bijections from both $X$ and $Y$ to the ordinal $|X|=|Y|$, and combining these bijections gives us a bijection between $X$ and $Y$.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      Wow that was easy - easier than I expected! Thanks for your help.
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:34










    • $begingroup$
      One question; why isn't this proof more 'popular'? There are various different proofs of this theorem and even the simplest of those (two) that I've been able to follow/understand are quite complicated and not much fun.
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:40










    • $begingroup$
      It is a fundamental result of cardinal arithmetic that works without the axiom of choice and can be used before one learns about well-orders. A way the usual proofs can be made less messy is by assuming one set is a subset of the other and the injection into the bigger set is the identity.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:43










    • $begingroup$
      Doesn't the fact that all cardinals are comparable depend on the axiom of choice? How can this proof work, as you say, without it?
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:52










    • $begingroup$
      I mean the usual Cantor-Bernstein theorem and proofs by back-and-forth or a fixed point argument. Te proof I've given depends of course on the axiom of choice.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:55













    3












    3








    3





    $begingroup$

    Using the axiom of choice, every set can be well ordered. For each set $X$, let $|X|$ be the smallest ordinal order-isomorphic to some well-ordering of $X$. If there is an injection $f:Yto X$, then $Y$ can be identified with a subset of $X$ and hence with a subset of $|X|$. The order type of this set is smaller or equal to $|X|$, hence $|Y|leq |X|$. If there is also an injection from $X$ to $Y$, we can conclude that $|X|leq|Y|$. Since the class of ordinals is well-ordered it satisfies anti-symmetry and we can conclude that $|X|=|Y|$. So there are bijections from both $X$ and $Y$ to the ordinal $|X|=|Y|$, and combining these bijections gives us a bijection between $X$ and $Y$.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    Using the axiom of choice, every set can be well ordered. For each set $X$, let $|X|$ be the smallest ordinal order-isomorphic to some well-ordering of $X$. If there is an injection $f:Yto X$, then $Y$ can be identified with a subset of $X$ and hence with a subset of $|X|$. The order type of this set is smaller or equal to $|X|$, hence $|Y|leq |X|$. If there is also an injection from $X$ to $Y$, we can conclude that $|X|leq|Y|$. Since the class of ordinals is well-ordered it satisfies anti-symmetry and we can conclude that $|X|=|Y|$. So there are bijections from both $X$ and $Y$ to the ordinal $|X|=|Y|$, and combining these bijections gives us a bijection between $X$ and $Y$.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Oct 31 '12 at 7:06

























    answered Oct 29 '12 at 16:30









    Michael GreineckerMichael Greinecker

    24.9k454106




    24.9k454106











    • $begingroup$
      Wow that was easy - easier than I expected! Thanks for your help.
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:34










    • $begingroup$
      One question; why isn't this proof more 'popular'? There are various different proofs of this theorem and even the simplest of those (two) that I've been able to follow/understand are quite complicated and not much fun.
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:40










    • $begingroup$
      It is a fundamental result of cardinal arithmetic that works without the axiom of choice and can be used before one learns about well-orders. A way the usual proofs can be made less messy is by assuming one set is a subset of the other and the injection into the bigger set is the identity.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:43










    • $begingroup$
      Doesn't the fact that all cardinals are comparable depend on the axiom of choice? How can this proof work, as you say, without it?
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:52










    • $begingroup$
      I mean the usual Cantor-Bernstein theorem and proofs by back-and-forth or a fixed point argument. Te proof I've given depends of course on the axiom of choice.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:55
















    • $begingroup$
      Wow that was easy - easier than I expected! Thanks for your help.
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:34










    • $begingroup$
      One question; why isn't this proof more 'popular'? There are various different proofs of this theorem and even the simplest of those (two) that I've been able to follow/understand are quite complicated and not much fun.
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:40










    • $begingroup$
      It is a fundamental result of cardinal arithmetic that works without the axiom of choice and can be used before one learns about well-orders. A way the usual proofs can be made less messy is by assuming one set is a subset of the other and the injection into the bigger set is the identity.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:43










    • $begingroup$
      Doesn't the fact that all cardinals are comparable depend on the axiom of choice? How can this proof work, as you say, without it?
      $endgroup$
      – Acid2
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:52










    • $begingroup$
      I mean the usual Cantor-Bernstein theorem and proofs by back-and-forth or a fixed point argument. Te proof I've given depends of course on the axiom of choice.
      $endgroup$
      – Michael Greinecker
      Oct 29 '12 at 16:55















    $begingroup$
    Wow that was easy - easier than I expected! Thanks for your help.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:34




    $begingroup$
    Wow that was easy - easier than I expected! Thanks for your help.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:34












    $begingroup$
    One question; why isn't this proof more 'popular'? There are various different proofs of this theorem and even the simplest of those (two) that I've been able to follow/understand are quite complicated and not much fun.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:40




    $begingroup$
    One question; why isn't this proof more 'popular'? There are various different proofs of this theorem and even the simplest of those (two) that I've been able to follow/understand are quite complicated and not much fun.
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:40












    $begingroup$
    It is a fundamental result of cardinal arithmetic that works without the axiom of choice and can be used before one learns about well-orders. A way the usual proofs can be made less messy is by assuming one set is a subset of the other and the injection into the bigger set is the identity.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:43




    $begingroup$
    It is a fundamental result of cardinal arithmetic that works without the axiom of choice and can be used before one learns about well-orders. A way the usual proofs can be made less messy is by assuming one set is a subset of the other and the injection into the bigger set is the identity.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:43












    $begingroup$
    Doesn't the fact that all cardinals are comparable depend on the axiom of choice? How can this proof work, as you say, without it?
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:52




    $begingroup$
    Doesn't the fact that all cardinals are comparable depend on the axiom of choice? How can this proof work, as you say, without it?
    $endgroup$
    – Acid2
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:52












    $begingroup$
    I mean the usual Cantor-Bernstein theorem and proofs by back-and-forth or a fixed point argument. Te proof I've given depends of course on the axiom of choice.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:55




    $begingroup$
    I mean the usual Cantor-Bernstein theorem and proofs by back-and-forth or a fixed point argument. Te proof I've given depends of course on the axiom of choice.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael Greinecker
    Oct 29 '12 at 16:55











    3












    $begingroup$

    Check http://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-0348-0224-6/page/1



    The details are quite different from those in the other answers here.



    To complete my answer:



    Cantor's original proof of the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem.



    First, let me comment on some of the points mentioned above.



    1. The question assumes that Cantor's original proof relied on the axiom of choice. But the axiom of choice emerged only in 1904, well after Cantor finished his research.


    2. Cantor mentioned the well-ordering principle only in his 1883 paper (the above referenced Über unendlich… paper). So it cannot be maintained that his view on the principle "oscillated".


    3. Cantor needed the well-ordering principle in order to establish the arithmetic operations between his transfinite numbers (which he later called ordinals), and not for trichotomy, which is not mentioned in 1883. With the well-ordering principle Cantor also tacitly assumed a numbering principle which provides that for every well-ordered set there is a transfinite number similar to it, which is thus its numbering (Anzahl). With his later definition of the transfinite numbers (ordinals) by abstraction, instead of the earlier generation principles, Cantor had no further need for the well-ordering principle and its ancillary numbering principle to provide for the arithmetic operations between ordinals. So Cantor dropped the well-ordering principle after 1883.


    4. Cantor stated the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem (CBT) in 1883 as an immediate corollary to several theorems that established that the second number-class. Thus CBT was established for sets of the power $aleph_1$, not for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and without assuming CH. CH is needed to apply the theorem to subsets of $mathbb R^n$ but Cantor never did that. In fact, he didn't have to for, I believe, Cantor had a direct proof for CBT for $mathbb R$ and thus for $mathbb R^n$ (in view of his results in 1878). See my book referenced above.


    5. Cantor's construction of the number-classes from 1883 can be generalized. The proof is by transfinite induction which Cantor used for other proofs as well without identifying the procedure explicitly. Note that there are in fact two inductive arguments in the proof: one over the index of the number-classes and a second over the numbers in every preceding number-class. The generalized CBT is a necessary lemma in the proof establishing the construction of the scale of number-classes. Again I must reference my book.


    6. In the referenced 1895 paper three versions of CBT appear: the quoted B, the version which was mentioned in the answer above as originating from 1882, and a third version denoted there E.


    7. Cantor presented all three versions as simple corollary to the theorem referenced above as trichotomy. There Cantor postponed the proof of trichotomy to until such time when the ascending sequence of cardinal numbers will be established. The ground work for that scale, namely the scale of the number-classes was established in the 1897 paper. However, Cantor did not go back to trichotomy and this created some confusion. Zermelo interpreted the situation as implying that Cantor could not prove trichotomy and his view was adopted by almost all commentators on Cantor.


    8. Cantor intended to publish a third sequel to the 1895, 1897 papers. We know that from his correspondence with Hilbert. There he presumably intended to fill the blanks he left around the trichotomy theorem. However, Cantor was hesitant to go ahead with the third sequel until he got Dedekind's approval to the ideas contained therein, but Dedekind refused to get involved. We know this again from Cantor's correspondence. The ideas which Cantor was afraid to publish were two: First, that there are inconsistent sets in mathematics. These are the classes of today. Had Cantor published his ideas, which may have originated already in 1883, perhaps the scare of the antinomies would have been avoided. Second, that a new axiom is necessary to introduce to mathematics. It was the statement presented as corollary D to trichotomy. In fact Cantor was ready to assume both D and CBT (corollary B) but fortunately proofs for CBT began to emerge in 1897 and so there was no need to take CBT as axiom. These axioms were hinted in a letter to Schoenflies of 1899.


    9. In light of the above it seems to me that the idea that Cantor presented CBT in 1895 as an open problem cannot be maintained. Notwithstanding this remark I do recommend that you should consult besides my book also Ferreiros 1999, Birkhäuser.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Link only answers are not really good; could you at least give a sketch of the argument?
      $endgroup$
      – egreg
      Feb 15 '14 at 18:28










    • $begingroup$
      Nice reference, I was not aware of it. Thanks!
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Feb 16 '14 at 8:16










    • $begingroup$
      One thing about the fact that Cantor's proof relied on the axiom of choice; note that in fact many proofs given before the foundational crisis of the late-19th and early-20th centuries were using certain axioms before these were formulated. Because mathematicians didn't really think in terms of axioms (many still don't) and formal definitions; but when that began, the proofs were analyzed and in some of them we found use of the axiom of choice (or other axioms), and in others we didn't. If a proof uses the axiom of choice, then it uses the axiom of choice. Regardless to its temporal origins.
      $endgroup$
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '14 at 17:14










    • $begingroup$
      Dear Arie, Many thanks for the expanded remarks.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      May 9 '14 at 22:48















    3












    $begingroup$

    Check http://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-0348-0224-6/page/1



    The details are quite different from those in the other answers here.



    To complete my answer:



    Cantor's original proof of the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem.



    First, let me comment on some of the points mentioned above.



    1. The question assumes that Cantor's original proof relied on the axiom of choice. But the axiom of choice emerged only in 1904, well after Cantor finished his research.


    2. Cantor mentioned the well-ordering principle only in his 1883 paper (the above referenced Über unendlich… paper). So it cannot be maintained that his view on the principle "oscillated".


    3. Cantor needed the well-ordering principle in order to establish the arithmetic operations between his transfinite numbers (which he later called ordinals), and not for trichotomy, which is not mentioned in 1883. With the well-ordering principle Cantor also tacitly assumed a numbering principle which provides that for every well-ordered set there is a transfinite number similar to it, which is thus its numbering (Anzahl). With his later definition of the transfinite numbers (ordinals) by abstraction, instead of the earlier generation principles, Cantor had no further need for the well-ordering principle and its ancillary numbering principle to provide for the arithmetic operations between ordinals. So Cantor dropped the well-ordering principle after 1883.


    4. Cantor stated the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem (CBT) in 1883 as an immediate corollary to several theorems that established that the second number-class. Thus CBT was established for sets of the power $aleph_1$, not for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and without assuming CH. CH is needed to apply the theorem to subsets of $mathbb R^n$ but Cantor never did that. In fact, he didn't have to for, I believe, Cantor had a direct proof for CBT for $mathbb R$ and thus for $mathbb R^n$ (in view of his results in 1878). See my book referenced above.


    5. Cantor's construction of the number-classes from 1883 can be generalized. The proof is by transfinite induction which Cantor used for other proofs as well without identifying the procedure explicitly. Note that there are in fact two inductive arguments in the proof: one over the index of the number-classes and a second over the numbers in every preceding number-class. The generalized CBT is a necessary lemma in the proof establishing the construction of the scale of number-classes. Again I must reference my book.


    6. In the referenced 1895 paper three versions of CBT appear: the quoted B, the version which was mentioned in the answer above as originating from 1882, and a third version denoted there E.


    7. Cantor presented all three versions as simple corollary to the theorem referenced above as trichotomy. There Cantor postponed the proof of trichotomy to until such time when the ascending sequence of cardinal numbers will be established. The ground work for that scale, namely the scale of the number-classes was established in the 1897 paper. However, Cantor did not go back to trichotomy and this created some confusion. Zermelo interpreted the situation as implying that Cantor could not prove trichotomy and his view was adopted by almost all commentators on Cantor.


    8. Cantor intended to publish a third sequel to the 1895, 1897 papers. We know that from his correspondence with Hilbert. There he presumably intended to fill the blanks he left around the trichotomy theorem. However, Cantor was hesitant to go ahead with the third sequel until he got Dedekind's approval to the ideas contained therein, but Dedekind refused to get involved. We know this again from Cantor's correspondence. The ideas which Cantor was afraid to publish were two: First, that there are inconsistent sets in mathematics. These are the classes of today. Had Cantor published his ideas, which may have originated already in 1883, perhaps the scare of the antinomies would have been avoided. Second, that a new axiom is necessary to introduce to mathematics. It was the statement presented as corollary D to trichotomy. In fact Cantor was ready to assume both D and CBT (corollary B) but fortunately proofs for CBT began to emerge in 1897 and so there was no need to take CBT as axiom. These axioms were hinted in a letter to Schoenflies of 1899.


    9. In light of the above it seems to me that the idea that Cantor presented CBT in 1895 as an open problem cannot be maintained. Notwithstanding this remark I do recommend that you should consult besides my book also Ferreiros 1999, Birkhäuser.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Link only answers are not really good; could you at least give a sketch of the argument?
      $endgroup$
      – egreg
      Feb 15 '14 at 18:28










    • $begingroup$
      Nice reference, I was not aware of it. Thanks!
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Feb 16 '14 at 8:16










    • $begingroup$
      One thing about the fact that Cantor's proof relied on the axiom of choice; note that in fact many proofs given before the foundational crisis of the late-19th and early-20th centuries were using certain axioms before these were formulated. Because mathematicians didn't really think in terms of axioms (many still don't) and formal definitions; but when that began, the proofs were analyzed and in some of them we found use of the axiom of choice (or other axioms), and in others we didn't. If a proof uses the axiom of choice, then it uses the axiom of choice. Regardless to its temporal origins.
      $endgroup$
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '14 at 17:14










    • $begingroup$
      Dear Arie, Many thanks for the expanded remarks.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      May 9 '14 at 22:48













    3












    3








    3





    $begingroup$

    Check http://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-0348-0224-6/page/1



    The details are quite different from those in the other answers here.



    To complete my answer:



    Cantor's original proof of the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem.



    First, let me comment on some of the points mentioned above.



    1. The question assumes that Cantor's original proof relied on the axiom of choice. But the axiom of choice emerged only in 1904, well after Cantor finished his research.


    2. Cantor mentioned the well-ordering principle only in his 1883 paper (the above referenced Über unendlich… paper). So it cannot be maintained that his view on the principle "oscillated".


    3. Cantor needed the well-ordering principle in order to establish the arithmetic operations between his transfinite numbers (which he later called ordinals), and not for trichotomy, which is not mentioned in 1883. With the well-ordering principle Cantor also tacitly assumed a numbering principle which provides that for every well-ordered set there is a transfinite number similar to it, which is thus its numbering (Anzahl). With his later definition of the transfinite numbers (ordinals) by abstraction, instead of the earlier generation principles, Cantor had no further need for the well-ordering principle and its ancillary numbering principle to provide for the arithmetic operations between ordinals. So Cantor dropped the well-ordering principle after 1883.


    4. Cantor stated the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem (CBT) in 1883 as an immediate corollary to several theorems that established that the second number-class. Thus CBT was established for sets of the power $aleph_1$, not for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and without assuming CH. CH is needed to apply the theorem to subsets of $mathbb R^n$ but Cantor never did that. In fact, he didn't have to for, I believe, Cantor had a direct proof for CBT for $mathbb R$ and thus for $mathbb R^n$ (in view of his results in 1878). See my book referenced above.


    5. Cantor's construction of the number-classes from 1883 can be generalized. The proof is by transfinite induction which Cantor used for other proofs as well without identifying the procedure explicitly. Note that there are in fact two inductive arguments in the proof: one over the index of the number-classes and a second over the numbers in every preceding number-class. The generalized CBT is a necessary lemma in the proof establishing the construction of the scale of number-classes. Again I must reference my book.


    6. In the referenced 1895 paper three versions of CBT appear: the quoted B, the version which was mentioned in the answer above as originating from 1882, and a third version denoted there E.


    7. Cantor presented all three versions as simple corollary to the theorem referenced above as trichotomy. There Cantor postponed the proof of trichotomy to until such time when the ascending sequence of cardinal numbers will be established. The ground work for that scale, namely the scale of the number-classes was established in the 1897 paper. However, Cantor did not go back to trichotomy and this created some confusion. Zermelo interpreted the situation as implying that Cantor could not prove trichotomy and his view was adopted by almost all commentators on Cantor.


    8. Cantor intended to publish a third sequel to the 1895, 1897 papers. We know that from his correspondence with Hilbert. There he presumably intended to fill the blanks he left around the trichotomy theorem. However, Cantor was hesitant to go ahead with the third sequel until he got Dedekind's approval to the ideas contained therein, but Dedekind refused to get involved. We know this again from Cantor's correspondence. The ideas which Cantor was afraid to publish were two: First, that there are inconsistent sets in mathematics. These are the classes of today. Had Cantor published his ideas, which may have originated already in 1883, perhaps the scare of the antinomies would have been avoided. Second, that a new axiom is necessary to introduce to mathematics. It was the statement presented as corollary D to trichotomy. In fact Cantor was ready to assume both D and CBT (corollary B) but fortunately proofs for CBT began to emerge in 1897 and so there was no need to take CBT as axiom. These axioms were hinted in a letter to Schoenflies of 1899.


    9. In light of the above it seems to me that the idea that Cantor presented CBT in 1895 as an open problem cannot be maintained. Notwithstanding this remark I do recommend that you should consult besides my book also Ferreiros 1999, Birkhäuser.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    Check http://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-3-0348-0224-6/page/1



    The details are quite different from those in the other answers here.



    To complete my answer:



    Cantor's original proof of the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem.



    First, let me comment on some of the points mentioned above.



    1. The question assumes that Cantor's original proof relied on the axiom of choice. But the axiom of choice emerged only in 1904, well after Cantor finished his research.


    2. Cantor mentioned the well-ordering principle only in his 1883 paper (the above referenced Über unendlich… paper). So it cannot be maintained that his view on the principle "oscillated".


    3. Cantor needed the well-ordering principle in order to establish the arithmetic operations between his transfinite numbers (which he later called ordinals), and not for trichotomy, which is not mentioned in 1883. With the well-ordering principle Cantor also tacitly assumed a numbering principle which provides that for every well-ordered set there is a transfinite number similar to it, which is thus its numbering (Anzahl). With his later definition of the transfinite numbers (ordinals) by abstraction, instead of the earlier generation principles, Cantor had no further need for the well-ordering principle and its ancillary numbering principle to provide for the arithmetic operations between ordinals. So Cantor dropped the well-ordering principle after 1883.


    4. Cantor stated the Cantor-Bernstein Theorem (CBT) in 1883 as an immediate corollary to several theorems that established that the second number-class. Thus CBT was established for sets of the power $aleph_1$, not for subsets of $mathbb R^n$, and without assuming CH. CH is needed to apply the theorem to subsets of $mathbb R^n$ but Cantor never did that. In fact, he didn't have to for, I believe, Cantor had a direct proof for CBT for $mathbb R$ and thus for $mathbb R^n$ (in view of his results in 1878). See my book referenced above.


    5. Cantor's construction of the number-classes from 1883 can be generalized. The proof is by transfinite induction which Cantor used for other proofs as well without identifying the procedure explicitly. Note that there are in fact two inductive arguments in the proof: one over the index of the number-classes and a second over the numbers in every preceding number-class. The generalized CBT is a necessary lemma in the proof establishing the construction of the scale of number-classes. Again I must reference my book.


    6. In the referenced 1895 paper three versions of CBT appear: the quoted B, the version which was mentioned in the answer above as originating from 1882, and a third version denoted there E.


    7. Cantor presented all three versions as simple corollary to the theorem referenced above as trichotomy. There Cantor postponed the proof of trichotomy to until such time when the ascending sequence of cardinal numbers will be established. The ground work for that scale, namely the scale of the number-classes was established in the 1897 paper. However, Cantor did not go back to trichotomy and this created some confusion. Zermelo interpreted the situation as implying that Cantor could not prove trichotomy and his view was adopted by almost all commentators on Cantor.


    8. Cantor intended to publish a third sequel to the 1895, 1897 papers. We know that from his correspondence with Hilbert. There he presumably intended to fill the blanks he left around the trichotomy theorem. However, Cantor was hesitant to go ahead with the third sequel until he got Dedekind's approval to the ideas contained therein, but Dedekind refused to get involved. We know this again from Cantor's correspondence. The ideas which Cantor was afraid to publish were two: First, that there are inconsistent sets in mathematics. These are the classes of today. Had Cantor published his ideas, which may have originated already in 1883, perhaps the scare of the antinomies would have been avoided. Second, that a new axiom is necessary to introduce to mathematics. It was the statement presented as corollary D to trichotomy. In fact Cantor was ready to assume both D and CBT (corollary B) but fortunately proofs for CBT began to emerge in 1897 and so there was no need to take CBT as axiom. These axioms were hinted in a letter to Schoenflies of 1899.


    9. In light of the above it seems to me that the idea that Cantor presented CBT in 1895 as an open problem cannot be maintained. Notwithstanding this remark I do recommend that you should consult besides my book also Ferreiros 1999, Birkhäuser.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited May 7 '14 at 21:08









    Andrés E. Caicedo

    65.8k8160251




    65.8k8160251










    answered Feb 15 '14 at 18:08









    ArikArik

    513




    513







    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Link only answers are not really good; could you at least give a sketch of the argument?
      $endgroup$
      – egreg
      Feb 15 '14 at 18:28










    • $begingroup$
      Nice reference, I was not aware of it. Thanks!
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Feb 16 '14 at 8:16










    • $begingroup$
      One thing about the fact that Cantor's proof relied on the axiom of choice; note that in fact many proofs given before the foundational crisis of the late-19th and early-20th centuries were using certain axioms before these were formulated. Because mathematicians didn't really think in terms of axioms (many still don't) and formal definitions; but when that began, the proofs were analyzed and in some of them we found use of the axiom of choice (or other axioms), and in others we didn't. If a proof uses the axiom of choice, then it uses the axiom of choice. Regardless to its temporal origins.
      $endgroup$
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '14 at 17:14










    • $begingroup$
      Dear Arie, Many thanks for the expanded remarks.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      May 9 '14 at 22:48












    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Link only answers are not really good; could you at least give a sketch of the argument?
      $endgroup$
      – egreg
      Feb 15 '14 at 18:28










    • $begingroup$
      Nice reference, I was not aware of it. Thanks!
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      Feb 16 '14 at 8:16










    • $begingroup$
      One thing about the fact that Cantor's proof relied on the axiom of choice; note that in fact many proofs given before the foundational crisis of the late-19th and early-20th centuries were using certain axioms before these were formulated. Because mathematicians didn't really think in terms of axioms (many still don't) and formal definitions; but when that began, the proofs were analyzed and in some of them we found use of the axiom of choice (or other axioms), and in others we didn't. If a proof uses the axiom of choice, then it uses the axiom of choice. Regardless to its temporal origins.
      $endgroup$
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '14 at 17:14










    • $begingroup$
      Dear Arie, Many thanks for the expanded remarks.
      $endgroup$
      – Andrés E. Caicedo
      May 9 '14 at 22:48







    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    Link only answers are not really good; could you at least give a sketch of the argument?
    $endgroup$
    – egreg
    Feb 15 '14 at 18:28




    $begingroup$
    Link only answers are not really good; could you at least give a sketch of the argument?
    $endgroup$
    – egreg
    Feb 15 '14 at 18:28












    $begingroup$
    Nice reference, I was not aware of it. Thanks!
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Feb 16 '14 at 8:16




    $begingroup$
    Nice reference, I was not aware of it. Thanks!
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    Feb 16 '14 at 8:16












    $begingroup$
    One thing about the fact that Cantor's proof relied on the axiom of choice; note that in fact many proofs given before the foundational crisis of the late-19th and early-20th centuries were using certain axioms before these were formulated. Because mathematicians didn't really think in terms of axioms (many still don't) and formal definitions; but when that began, the proofs were analyzed and in some of them we found use of the axiom of choice (or other axioms), and in others we didn't. If a proof uses the axiom of choice, then it uses the axiom of choice. Regardless to its temporal origins.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '14 at 17:14




    $begingroup$
    One thing about the fact that Cantor's proof relied on the axiom of choice; note that in fact many proofs given before the foundational crisis of the late-19th and early-20th centuries were using certain axioms before these were formulated. Because mathematicians didn't really think in terms of axioms (many still don't) and formal definitions; but when that began, the proofs were analyzed and in some of them we found use of the axiom of choice (or other axioms), and in others we didn't. If a proof uses the axiom of choice, then it uses the axiom of choice. Regardless to its temporal origins.
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '14 at 17:14












    $begingroup$
    Dear Arie, Many thanks for the expanded remarks.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    May 9 '14 at 22:48




    $begingroup$
    Dear Arie, Many thanks for the expanded remarks.
    $endgroup$
    – Andrés E. Caicedo
    May 9 '14 at 22:48











    2












    $begingroup$

    Cantor's original proof relies on the well-ordering principle, stating that every set can be well-ordered.



    If $Aleq B$, namely there is an injection from $A$ into $B$; and $Bleq A$, so there is also an injection from $B$ into $A$, using the well-ordering principle let $alpha$ be the least ordinal such that $alpha$ has a bijection with $A$; and let $beta$ be the least ordinal which has a bijection with $B$.



    Now note that a subset of an ordinal can be "collapsed" and be put in bijection with an ordinal, not necessarily a smaller one though. If $gamma<alpha$ was such that there was an injection from $A$ into $gamma$ then by collapsing the range of this injection we would get a bijection of $A$ with an ordinal $leqgamma$. Therefore $A$ cannot be injected into any smaller ordinal than $alpha$ or we would contradict the minimality of $alpha$, and the same argument shows that $B$ cannot be injected into any ordinal smaller than $beta$.



    By composing the injections between $A$ and $B$, and the bijections with $alpha$ and $beta$ we have an injection from $A$ into $beta$ and from $B$ into $alpha$. The above argument shows that we have $alphaleqbeta$ as well $betaleqalpha$. Therefore we must have $alpha=beta$.



    By composing the bijections from $A$ to $alpha$ and from $alpha$ to $B$ we have a bijection between $A$ and $B$ as wanted.



    See also: Cantor-Bernstein-like theorem: If $fcolon Ato B$ is injection and $gcolon Ato B$ is surjective, can we prove there is a bijection as well?






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$

















      2












      $begingroup$

      Cantor's original proof relies on the well-ordering principle, stating that every set can be well-ordered.



      If $Aleq B$, namely there is an injection from $A$ into $B$; and $Bleq A$, so there is also an injection from $B$ into $A$, using the well-ordering principle let $alpha$ be the least ordinal such that $alpha$ has a bijection with $A$; and let $beta$ be the least ordinal which has a bijection with $B$.



      Now note that a subset of an ordinal can be "collapsed" and be put in bijection with an ordinal, not necessarily a smaller one though. If $gamma<alpha$ was such that there was an injection from $A$ into $gamma$ then by collapsing the range of this injection we would get a bijection of $A$ with an ordinal $leqgamma$. Therefore $A$ cannot be injected into any smaller ordinal than $alpha$ or we would contradict the minimality of $alpha$, and the same argument shows that $B$ cannot be injected into any ordinal smaller than $beta$.



      By composing the injections between $A$ and $B$, and the bijections with $alpha$ and $beta$ we have an injection from $A$ into $beta$ and from $B$ into $alpha$. The above argument shows that we have $alphaleqbeta$ as well $betaleqalpha$. Therefore we must have $alpha=beta$.



      By composing the bijections from $A$ to $alpha$ and from $alpha$ to $B$ we have a bijection between $A$ and $B$ as wanted.



      See also: Cantor-Bernstein-like theorem: If $fcolon Ato B$ is injection and $gcolon Ato B$ is surjective, can we prove there is a bijection as well?






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$















        2












        2








        2





        $begingroup$

        Cantor's original proof relies on the well-ordering principle, stating that every set can be well-ordered.



        If $Aleq B$, namely there is an injection from $A$ into $B$; and $Bleq A$, so there is also an injection from $B$ into $A$, using the well-ordering principle let $alpha$ be the least ordinal such that $alpha$ has a bijection with $A$; and let $beta$ be the least ordinal which has a bijection with $B$.



        Now note that a subset of an ordinal can be "collapsed" and be put in bijection with an ordinal, not necessarily a smaller one though. If $gamma<alpha$ was such that there was an injection from $A$ into $gamma$ then by collapsing the range of this injection we would get a bijection of $A$ with an ordinal $leqgamma$. Therefore $A$ cannot be injected into any smaller ordinal than $alpha$ or we would contradict the minimality of $alpha$, and the same argument shows that $B$ cannot be injected into any ordinal smaller than $beta$.



        By composing the injections between $A$ and $B$, and the bijections with $alpha$ and $beta$ we have an injection from $A$ into $beta$ and from $B$ into $alpha$. The above argument shows that we have $alphaleqbeta$ as well $betaleqalpha$. Therefore we must have $alpha=beta$.



        By composing the bijections from $A$ to $alpha$ and from $alpha$ to $B$ we have a bijection between $A$ and $B$ as wanted.



        See also: Cantor-Bernstein-like theorem: If $fcolon Ato B$ is injection and $gcolon Ato B$ is surjective, can we prove there is a bijection as well?






        share|cite|improve this answer











        $endgroup$



        Cantor's original proof relies on the well-ordering principle, stating that every set can be well-ordered.



        If $Aleq B$, namely there is an injection from $A$ into $B$; and $Bleq A$, so there is also an injection from $B$ into $A$, using the well-ordering principle let $alpha$ be the least ordinal such that $alpha$ has a bijection with $A$; and let $beta$ be the least ordinal which has a bijection with $B$.



        Now note that a subset of an ordinal can be "collapsed" and be put in bijection with an ordinal, not necessarily a smaller one though. If $gamma<alpha$ was such that there was an injection from $A$ into $gamma$ then by collapsing the range of this injection we would get a bijection of $A$ with an ordinal $leqgamma$. Therefore $A$ cannot be injected into any smaller ordinal than $alpha$ or we would contradict the minimality of $alpha$, and the same argument shows that $B$ cannot be injected into any ordinal smaller than $beta$.



        By composing the injections between $A$ and $B$, and the bijections with $alpha$ and $beta$ we have an injection from $A$ into $beta$ and from $B$ into $alpha$. The above argument shows that we have $alphaleqbeta$ as well $betaleqalpha$. Therefore we must have $alpha=beta$.



        By composing the bijections from $A$ to $alpha$ and from $alpha$ to $B$ we have a bijection between $A$ and $B$ as wanted.



        See also: Cantor-Bernstein-like theorem: If $fcolon Ato B$ is injection and $gcolon Ato B$ is surjective, can we prove there is a bijection as well?







        share|cite|improve this answer














        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer








        edited Apr 13 '17 at 12:20









        Community

        1




        1










        answered Oct 29 '12 at 17:11









        Asaf KaragilaAsaf Karagila

        306k33438769




        306k33438769



























            draft saved

            draft discarded
















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid


            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f223587%2flooking-for-cantors-original-proof-of-the-cantor-bernstein-theorem-that-relies%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Lowndes Grove History Architecture References Navigation menu32°48′6″N 79°57′58″W / 32.80167°N 79.96611°W / 32.80167; -79.9661132°48′6″N 79°57′58″W / 32.80167°N 79.96611°W / 32.80167; -79.9661178002500"National Register Information System"Historic houses of South Carolina"Lowndes Grove""+32° 48' 6.00", −79° 57' 58.00""Lowndes Grove, Charleston County (260 St. Margaret St., Charleston)""Lowndes Grove"The Charleston ExpositionIt Happened in South Carolina"Lowndes Grove (House), Saint Margaret Street & Sixth Avenue, Charleston, Charleston County, SC(Photographs)"Plantations of the Carolina Low Countrye

            random experiment with two different functions on unit interval Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern)Random variable and probability space notionsRandom Walk with EdgesFinding functions where the increase over a random interval is Poisson distributedNumber of days until dayCan an observed event in fact be of zero probability?Unit random processmodels of coins and uniform distributionHow to get the number of successes given $n$ trials , probability $P$ and a random variable $X$Absorbing Markov chain in a computer. Is “almost every” turned into always convergence in computer executions?Stopped random walk is not uniformly integrable

            How should I support this large drywall patch? Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern) Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Unicorn Meta Zoo #1: Why another podcast?How do I cover large gaps in drywall?How do I keep drywall around a patch from crumbling?Can I glue a second layer of drywall?How to patch long strip on drywall?Large drywall patch: how to avoid bulging seams?Drywall Mesh Patch vs. Bulge? To remove or not to remove?How to fix this drywall job?Prep drywall before backsplashWhat's the best way to fix this horrible drywall patch job?Drywall patching using 3M Patch Plus Primer